PHI 201  Philosophy of Human Nature

Sample Discussion Preparation Report
Plato's Phaedo, 57a-70b

Reading Summary

The first part of Plato's Phaedo dramatically sets up the question that the dialogue will consider: the nature and immortality of the soul.  Socrates has been in prison awaiting execution, and when the day arrives, his friends gather to converse with him.  Discussion naturally turns to Socrates' oddly positive attitude about his impending death.  Socrates explains that the wise person will not fear death, but will welcome it as a release from the distractions and deceptions of the body.  Socrates states in a key passage that he wants to explain his view that "a man who has truly spent his life in philosophy is probably right to be of good cheer in the face of death and to be very hopeful that after death he will attain the greatest blessings yonder" (63e).  His argument begins with the claim that death is nothing more than the separation of soul and body (64c).  Since the true philosopher is the one who seeks wisdom, and since the body impedes that search, release from the body is a good thing (64e-67d).  Despite this optimistic view, Socrates does argue, on religious grounds, that we should not hasten death by suicide, for we belong to the gods (61c-62c).

Throughout the first part of the dialogue Plato provides several dramatic hints to the reader to think about Pythagorean ideas of the immortality of the soul and the idea that the soul must be purified from bodily taint in this life.  The reading selection ends with one of Socrates' interlocutors, Cebes, pointing out that Socrates' attitude toward death is appropriate only if the soul survives death (69e-70b).  This sets up the problem that the remainder of the dialogue addresses.
 

Significant Problems

Socrates' definition of death as the separation of soul from body (64c) seems to presume the existence of the soul.  Perhaps Socrates only means that a living thing is a body that is active, and that by soul we mean only whatever it is that makes the body alive (whether it is a thing or not).  This point should be clarified in what we read later.

Socrates' claim that real knowledge cannot come from the senses discounts what we ordinarily count as knowledge.  Most such knowledge, such as knowledge of colors, physical objects, other people, does come from our use of the bodily senses.  But Socrates, like the Pythagoreans, thinks that real knowledge is apprehension of concepts like numbers.  His own examples are the "ideal realities" of the Just, the Beautiful, and the Good (65d-e), which are the conceptual standards we use to identify just things, beautiful things, and good things in our experience.
 

Critical Comment

At this point Socrates really has only outlined his position.  But it is clear that his notion of human nature includes the claim that human beings are composed of souls and bodies, that souls somehow survive death, and that bodies are in important ways inferior to souls.  The question raised by Cebes at the end of the passage suggests that some justification for these views is necessary if Socrates' positive attitude is to be anything more than "good hope."  It is also worth noting that Socrates' view is explicitly opposed to the common view of humans, especially his claim that real happiness involves ignoring bodily desires and pleasures.

Back to PHIL 201 Philosophy of Human Nature Page

Back to David H. Calhoun's Home Page
Copyright 1998 by David Calhoun.  This page last updated on March 15, 1998.