![]() Aristotle |
Aristotle
Nicomachean Ethics VIII-IX On Friendship |
Contact me by email at calhoun@calvin.gonzaga.edu |
Aristotle
Nicomachean Ethics, Books VIII and IX (Friendship)
Translated by W. D. Ross
NOTE TO STUDENTS: Since this
electronic version of the text does not have Bekker numbers (the marginal
numbers found in most scholarly printed versions of Aristotle's texts)
you should not use it for writing a paper. If you wish to write a
paper on Aristotle's theory of friendship you should consult a more recent
translation of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics that includes Bekker numbers
for proper citation reference. A particularly good version is Terence
Irwin's translation published by Hackett.
1
AFTER what we have said, a discussion of friendship
would naturally follow, since it is a virtue or implies virtue, and is
besides most necessary with a view to living. For without friends no one
would choose to live, though he had all other goods; even rich men and
those in possession of office and of dominating power are thought to need
friends most of all; for what is the use of such prosperity without the
opportunity of beneficence, which is exercised chiefly and in its most
laudable form towards friends? Or how can prosperity be guarded and preserved
without friends? The greater it is, the more exposed is it to risk. And
in poverty and in other misfortunes men think friends are the only refuge.
It helps the young, too, to keep from error; it aids older people by ministering
to their needs and supplementing the activities that are failing from weakness;
those in the prime of life it stimulates to noble actions-'two going together'-for
with friends men are more able both to think and to act. Again, parent
seems by nature to feel it for offspring and offspring for parent, not
only among men but among birds and among most animals; it is felt mutually
by members of the same race, and especially by men, whence we praise lovers
of their fellowmen. We may even in our travels how near and dear every
man is to every other. Friendship seems too to hold states together, and
lawgivers to care more for it than for justice; for unanimity seems to
be something like friendship, and this they aim at most of all, and expel
faction as their worst enemy; and when men are friends they have no need
of justice, while when they are just they need friendship as well, and
the truest form of justice is thought to be a friendly quality.
But it is not only necessary but also noble;
for we praise those who love their friends, and it is thought to be a fine
thing to have many friends; and again we think it is the same people that
are good men and are friends.
Not a few things about friendship are matters
of debate. Some define it as a kind of likeness and say like people are
friends, whence come the sayings 'like to like', 'birds of a feather flock
together', and so on; others on the contrary say 'two of a trade never
agree'. On this very question they inquire for deeper and more physical
causes, Euripides saying that 'parched earth loves the rain, and stately
heaven when filled with rain loves to fall to earth', and Heraclitus that
'it is what opposes that helps' and 'from different tones comes the fairest
tune' and 'all things are produced through strife'; while Empedocles, as
well as others, expresses the opposite view that like aims at like. The
physical problems we may leave alone (for they do not belong to the present
inquiry); let us examine those which are human and involve character and
feeling, e.g. whether friendship can arise between any two people or people
cannot be friends if they are wicked, and whether there is one species
of friendship or more than one. Those who think there is only one because
it admits of degrees have relied on an inadequate indication; for even
things different in species admit of degree. We have discussed this matter
previously.
2
The kinds of friendship may perhaps be cleared
up if we first come to know the object of love. For not everything seems
to be loved but only the lovable, and this is good, pleasant, or useful;
but it would seem to be that by which some good or pleasure is produced
that is useful, so that it is the good and the useful that are lovable
as ends. Do men love, then, the good, or what is good for them? These sometimes
clash. So too with regard to the pleasant. Now it is thought that each
loves what is good for himself, and that the good is without qualification
lovable, and what is good for each man is lovable for him; but each man
loves not what is good for him but what seems good. This however will make
no difference; we shall just have to say that this is 'that which seems
lovable'. Now there are three grounds on which people love; of the love
of lifeless objects we do not use the word 'friendship'; for it is not
mutual love, nor is there a wishing of good to the other (for it would
surely be ridiculous to wish wine well; if one wishes anything for it,
it is that it may keep, so that one may have it oneself); but to a friend
we say we ought to wish what is good for his sake. But to those who thus
wish good we ascribe only goodwill, if the wish is not reciprocated; goodwill
when it is reciprocal being friendship. Or must we add 'when it is recognized'?
For many people have goodwill to those whom they have not seen but judge
to be good or useful; and one of these might return this feeling. These
people seem to bear goodwill to each other; but how could one call them
friends when they do not know their mutual feelings? To be friends, then,
the must be mutually recognized as bearing goodwill and wishing well to
each other for one of the aforesaid reasons.
3
Now these reasons differ from each other in
kind; so, therefore, do the corresponding forms of love and friendship.
There are therefore three kinds of friendship, equal in number to the things
that are lovable; for with respect to each there is a mutual and recognized
love, and those who love each other wish well to each other in that respect
in which they love one another. Now those who love each other for their
utility do not love each other for themselves but in virtue of some good
which they get from each other. So too with those who love for the sake
of pleasure; it is not for their character that men love ready-witted people,
but because they find them pleasant. Therefore those who love for the sake
of utility love for the sake of what is good for themselves, and those
who love for the sake of pleasure do so for the sake of what is pleasant
to themselves, and not in so far as the other is the person loved but in
so far as he is useful or pleasant. And thus these friendships are only
incidental; for it is not as being the man he is that the loved person
is loved, but as providing some good or pleasure. Such friendships, then,
are easily dissolved, if the parties do not remain like themselves; for
if the one party is no longer pleasant or useful the other ceases to love
him.
Now the useful is not permanent but is always
changing. Thus when the motive of the friendship is done away, the friendship
is dissolved, inasmuch as it existed only for the ends in question. This
kind of friendship seems to exist chiefly between old people (for at that
age people pursue not the pleasant but the useful) and, of those who are
in their prime or young, between those who pursue utility. And such people
do not live much with each other either; for sometimes they do not even
find each other pleasant; therefore they do not need such companionship
unless they are useful to each other; for they are pleasant to each other
only in so far as they rouse in each other hopes of something good to come.
Among such friendships people also class the friendship of a host and guest.
On the other hand the friendship of young people seems to aim at pleasure;
for they live under the guidance of emotion, and pursue above all what
is pleasant to themselves and what is immediately before them; but with
increasing age their pleasures become different. This is why they quickly
become friends and quickly cease to be so; their friendship changes with
the object that is found pleasant, and such pleasure alters quickly. Young
people are amorous too; for the greater part of the friendship of love
depends on emotion and aims at pleasure; this is why they fall in love
and quickly fall out of love, changing often within a single day. But these
people do wish to spend their days and lives together; for it is thus that
they attain the purpose of their friendship.
Perfect friendship is the friendship of men
who are good, and alike in virtue; for these wish well alike to each other
qua good, and they are good themselves. Now those who wish well to their
friends for their sake are most truly friends; for they do this by reason
of own nature and not incidentally; therefore their friendship lasts as
long as they are good-and goodness is an enduring thing. And each is good
without qualification and to his friend, for the good are both good without
qualification and useful to each other. So too they are pleasant; for the
good are pleasant both without qualification and to each other, since to
each his own activities and others like them are pleasurable, and the actions
of the good are the same or like. And such a friendship is as might be
expected permanent, since there meet in it all the qualities that friends
should have. For all friendship is for the sake of good or of pleasure-good
or pleasure either in the abstract or such as will be enjoyed by him who
has the friendly feeling-and is based on a certain resemblance; and to
a friendship of good men all the qualities we have named belong in virtue
of the nature of the friends themselves; for in the case of this kind of
friendship the other qualities also are alike in both friends, and that
which is good without qualification is also without qualification pleasant,
and these are the most lovable qualities. Love and friendship therefore
are found most and in their best form between such men.
But it is natural that such friendships should
be infrequent; for such men are rare. Further, such friendship requires
time and familiarity; as the proverb says, men cannot know each other till
they have 'eaten salt together'; nor can they admit each other to friendship
or be friends till each has been found lovable and been trusted by each.
Those who quickly show the marks of friendship to each other wish to be
friends, but are not friends unless they both are lovable and know the
fact; for a wish for friendship may arise quickly, but friendship does
not.
4
This kind of friendship, then, is perfect
both in respect of duration and in all other respects, and in it each gets
from each in all respects the same as, or something like what, he gives;
which is what ought to happen between friends. Friendship for the sake
of pleasure bears a resemblance to this kind; for good people too are pleasant
to each other. So too does friendship for the sake of utility; for the
good are also useful to each other. Among men of these inferior sorts too,
friendships are most permanent when the friends get the same thing from
each other (e.g. pleasure), and not only that but also from the same source,
as happens between readywitted people, not as happens between lover and
beloved. For these do not take pleasure in the same things, but the one
in seeing the beloved and the other in receiving attentions from his lover;
and when the bloom of youth is passing the friendship sometimes passes
too (for the one finds no pleasure in the sight of the other, and the other
gets no attentions from the first); but many lovers on the other hand are
constant, if familiarity has led them to love each other's characters,
these being alike. But those who exchange not pleasure but utility in their
amour are both less truly friends and less constant. Those who are friends
for the sake of utility part when the advantage is at an end; for they
were lovers not of each other but of profit.
For the sake of pleasure or utility, then,
even bad men may be friends of each other, or good men of bad, or one who
is neither good nor bad may be a friend to any sort of person, but for
their own sake clearly only good men can be friends; for bad men do not
delight in each other unless some advantage come of the relation.
The friendship of the good too and this alone
is proof against slander; for it is not easy to trust any one talk about
a man who has long been tested by oneself; and it is among good men that
trust and the feeling that 'he would never wrong me' and all the other
things that are demanded in true friendship are found. In the other kinds
of friendship, however, there is nothing to prevent these evils arising.
For men apply the name of friends even to those whose motive is utility,
in which sense states are said to be friendly (for the alliances of states
seem to aim at advantage), and to those who love each other for the sake
of pleasure, in which sense children are called friends. Therefore we too
ought perhaps to call such people friends, and say that there are several
kinds of friendship-firstly and in the proper sense that of good men qua
good, and by analogy the other kinds; for it is in virtue of something
good and something akin to what is found in true friendship that they are
friends, since even the pleasant is good for the lovers of pleasure. But
these two kinds of friendship are not often united, nor do the same people
become friends for the sake of utility and of pleasure; for things that
are only incidentally connected are not often coupled together.
Friendship being divided into these kinds,
bad men will be friends for the sake of pleasure or of utility, being in
this respect like each other, but good men will be friends for their own
sake, i.e. in virtue of their goodness. These, then, are friends without
qualification; the others are friends incidentally and through a resemblance
to these.
5
As in regard to the virtues some men are called
good in respect of a state of character, others in respect of an activity,
so too in the case of friendship; for those who live together delight in
each other and confer benefits on each other, but those who are asleep
or locally separated are not performing, but are disposed to perform, the
activities of friendship; distance does not break off the friendship absolutely,
but only the activity of it. But if the absence is lasting, it seems actually
to make men forget their friendship; hence the saying 'out of sight, out
of mind'. Neither old people nor sour people seem to make friends easily;
for there is little that is pleasant in them, and no one can spend his
days with one whose company is painful, or not pleasant, since nature seems
above all to avoid the painful and to aim at the pleasant. Those, however,
who approve of each other but do not live together seem to be well-disposed
rather than actual friends. For there is nothing so characteristic of friends
as living together (since while it people who are in need that desire benefits,
even those who are supremely happy desire to spend their days together;
for solitude suits such people least of all); but people cannot live together
if they are not pleasant and do not enjoy the same things, as friends who
are companions seem to do.
The truest friendship, then, is that of the
good, as we have frequently said; for that which is without qualification
good or pleasant seems to be lovable and desirable, and for each person
that which is good or pleasant to him; and the good man is lovable and
desirable to the good man for both these reasons. Now it looks as if love
were a feeling, friendship a state of character; for love may be felt just
as much towards lifeless things, but mutual love involves choice and choice
springs from a state of character; and men wish well to those whom they
love, for their sake, not as a result of feeling but as a result of a state
of character. And in loving a friend men love what is good for themselves;
for the good man in becoming a friend becomes a good to his friend. Each,
then, both loves what is good for himself, and makes an equal return in
goodwill and in pleasantness; for friendship is said to be equality, and
both of these are found most in the friendship of the good.
6
Between sour and elderly people friendship
arises less readily, inasmuch as they are less good-tempered and enjoy
companionship less; for these are thou to be the greatest marks of friendship
productive of it. This is why, while men become friends quickly, old men
do not; it is because men do not become friends with those in whom they
do not delight; and similarly sour people do not quickly make friends either.
But such men may bear goodwill to each other; for they wish one another
well and aid one another in need; but they are hardly friends because they
do not spend their days together nor delight in each other, and these are
thought the greatest marks of friendship.
One cannot be a friend to many people in the
sense of having friendship of the perfect type with them, just as one cannot
be in love with many people at once (for love is a sort of excess of feeling,
and it is the nature of such only to be felt towards one person); and it
is not easy for many people at the same time to please the same person
very greatly, or perhaps even to be good in his eyes. One must, too, acquire
some experience of the other person and become familiar with him, and that
is very hard. But with a view to utility or pleasure it is possible that
many people should please one; for many people are useful or pleasant,
and these services take little time.
Of these two kinds that which is for the sake
of pleasure is the more like friendship, when both parties get the same
things from each other and delight in each other or in the things, as in
the friendships of the young; for generosity is more found in such friendships.
Friendship based on utility is for the commercially minded. People who
are supremely happy, too, have no need of useful friends, but do need pleasant
friends; for they wish to live with some one and, though they can endure
for a short time what is painful, no one could put up with it continuously,
nor even with the Good itself if it were painful to him; this is why they
look out for friends who are pleasant. Perhaps they should look out for
friends who, being pleasant, are also good, and good for them too; for
so they will have all the characteristics that friends should have.
People in positions of authority seem to have
friends who fall into distinct classes; some people are useful to them
and others are pleasant, but the same people are rarely both; for they
seek neither those whose pleasantness is accompanied by virtue nor those
whose utility is with a view to noble objects, but in their desire for
pleasure they seek for ready-witted people, and their other friends they
choose as being clever at doing what they are told, and these characteristics
are rarely combined. Now we have said that the good man is at the same
time pleasant and useful; but such a man does not become the friend of
one who surpasses him in station, unless he is surpassed also in virtue;
if this is not so, he does not establish equality by being proportionally
exceeded in both respects. But people who surpass him in both respects
are not so easy to find.
However that may be, the aforesaid friendships
involve equality; for the friends get the same things from one another
and wish the same things for one another, or exchange one thing for another,
e.g. pleasure for utility; we have said, however, that they are both less
truly friendships and less permanent.
But it is from their likeness and their unlikeness
to the same thing that they are thought both to be and not to be friendships.
It is by their likeness to the friendship of virtue that they seem to be
friendships (for one of them involves pleasure and the other utility, and
these characteristics belong to the friendship of virtue as well); while
it is because the friendship of virtue is proof against slander and permanent,
while these quickly change (besides differing from the former in many other
respects), that they appear not to be friendships; i.e. it is because of
their unlikeness to the friendship of virtue.
7
But there is another kind of friendship, viz.
that which involves an inequality between the parties, e.g. that of father
to son and in general of elder to younger, that of man to wife and in general
that of ruler to subject. And these friendships differ also from each other;
for it is not the same that exists between parents and children and between
rulers and subjects, nor is even that of father to son the same as that
of son to father, nor that of husband to wife the same as that of wife
to husband. For the virtue and the function of each of these is different,
and so are the reasons for which they love; the love and the friendship
are therefore different also. Each party, then, neither gets the same from
the other, nor ought to seek it; but when children render to parents what
they ought to render to those who brought them into the world, and parents
render what they should to their children, the friendship of such persons
will be abiding and excellent. In all friendships implying inequality the
love also should be proportional, i.e. the better should be more loved
than he loves, and so should the more useful, and similarly in each of
the other cases; for when the love is in proportion to the merit of the
parties, then in a sense arises equality, which is certainly held to be
characteristic of friendship.
But equality does not seem to take the same
form in acts of justice and in friendship; for in acts of justice what
is equal in the primary sense is that which is in proportion to merit,
while quantitative equality is secondary, but in friendship quantitative
equality is primary and proportion to merit secondary. This becomes clear
if there is a great interval in respect of virtue or vice or wealth or
anything else between the parties; for then they are no longer friends,
and do not even expect to be so. And this is most manifest in the case
of the gods; for they surpass us most decisively in all good things. But
it is clear also in the case of kings; for with them, too, men who are
much their inferiors do not expect to be friends; nor do men of no account
expect to be friends with the best or wisest men. In such cases it is not
possible to define exactly up to what point friends can remain friends;
for much can be taken away and friendship remain, but when one party is
removed to a great distance, as God is, the possibility of friendship ceases.
This is in fact the origin of the question whether friends really wish
for their friends the greatest goods, e.g. that of being gods; since in
that case their friends will no longer be friends to them, and therefore
will not be good things for them (for friends are good things). The answer
is that if we were right in saying that friend wishes good to friend for
his sake, his friend must remain the sort of being he is, whatever that
may be; therefore it is for him oily so long as he remains a man that he
will wish the greatest goods. But perhaps not all the greatest goods; for
it is for himself most of all that each man wishes what is good.
8
Most people seem, owing to ambition, to wish
to be loved rather than to love; which is why most men love flattery; for
the flatterer is a friend in an inferior position, or pretends to be such
and to love more than he is loved; and being loved seems to be akin to
being honoured, and this is what most people aim at. But it seems to be
not for its own sake that people choose honour, but incidentally. For most
people enjoy being honoured by those in positions of authority because
of their hopes (for they think that if they want anything they will get
it from them; and therefore they delight in honour as a token of favour
to come); while those who desire honour from good men, and men who know,
are aiming at confirming their own opinion of themselves; they delight
in honour, therefore, because they believe in their own goodness on the
strength of the judgement of those who speak about them. In being loved,
on the other hand, people delight for its own sake; whence it would seem
to be better than being honoured, and friendship to be desirable in itself.
But it seems to lie in loving rather than in being loved, as is indicated
by the delight mothers take in loving; for some mothers hand over their
children to be brought up, and so long as they know their fate they love
them and do not seek to be loved in return (if they cannot have both),
but seem to be satisfied if they see them prospering; and they themselves
love their children even if these owing to their ignorance give them nothing
of a mother's due. Now since friendship depends more on loving, and it
is those who love their friends that are praised, loving seems to be the
characteristic virtue of friends, so that it is only those in whom this
is found in due measure that are lasting friends, and only their friendship
that endures.
It is in this way more than any other that
even unequals can be friends; they can be equalized. Now equality and likeness
are friendship, and especially the likeness of those who are like in virtue;
for being steadfast in themselves they hold fast to each other, and neither
ask nor give base services, but (one may say) even prevent them; for it
is characteristic of good men neither to go wrong themselves nor to let
their friends do so. But wicked men have no steadfastness (for they do
not remain even like to themselves), but become friends for a short time
because they delight in each other's wickedness. Friends who are useful
or pleasant last longer; i.e. as long as they provide each other with enjoyments
or advantages. Friendship for utility's sake seems to be that which most
easily exists between contraries, e.g. between poor and rich, between ignorant
and learned; for what a man actually lacks he aims at, and one gives something
else in return. But under this head, too, might bring lover and beloved,
beautiful and ugly. This is why lovers sometimes seem ridiculous, when
they demand to be loved as they love; if they are equally lovable their
claim can perhaps be justified, but when they have nothing lovable about
them it is ridiculous. Perhaps, however, contrary does not even aim at
contrary by its own nature, but only incidentally, the desire being for
what is intermediate; for that is what is good, e.g. it is good for the
dry not to become wet but to come to the intermediate state, and similarly
with the hot and in all other cases. These subjects we may dismiss; for
they are indeed somewhat foreign to our inquiry.
9
Friendship and justice seem, as we have said
at the outset of our discussion, to be concerned with the same objects
and exhibited between the same persons. For in every community there is
thought to be some form of justice, and friendship too; at least men address
as friends their fellow-voyagers and fellowsoldiers, and so too those associated
with them in any other kind of community. And the extent of their association
is the extent of their friendship, as it is the extent to which justice
exists between them. And the proverb 'what friends have is common property'
expresses the truth; for friendship depends on community. Now brothers
and comrades have all things in common, but the others to whom we have
referred have definite things in common-some more things, others fewer;
for of friendships, too, some are more and others less truly friendships.
And the claims of justice differ too; the duties of parents to children,
and those of brothers to each other are not the same, nor those of comrades
and those of fellow-citizens, and so, too, with the other kinds of friendship.
There is a difference, therefore, also between the acts that are unjust
towards each of these classes of associates, and the injustice increases
by being exhibited towards those who are friends in a fuller sense; e.g.
it is a more terrible thing to defraud a comrade than a fellow-citizen,
more terrible not to help a brother than a stranger, and more terrible
to wound a father than any one else. And the demands of justice also seem
to increase with the intensity of the friendship, which implies that friendship
and justice exist between the same persons and have an equal extension.
Now all forms of community are like parts
of the political community; for men journey together with a view to some
particular advantage, and to provide something that they need for the purposes
of life; and it is for the sake of advantage that the political community
too seems both to have come together originally and to endure, for this
is what legislators aim at, and they call just that which is to the common
advantage. Now the other communities aim at advantage bit by bit, e.g.
sailors at what is advantageous on a voyage with a view to making money
or something of the kind, fellow-soldiers at what is advantageous in war,
whether it is wealth or victory or the taking of a city that they seek,
and members of tribes and demes act similarly (Some communities seem to
arise for the sake or pleasure, viz. religious guilds and social clubs;
for these exist respectively for the sake of offering sacrifice and of
companionship. But all these seem to fall under the political community;
for it aims not at present advantage but at what is advantageous for life
as a whole), offering sacrifices and arranging gatherings for the purpose,
and assigning honours to the gods, and providing pleasant relaxations for
themselves. For the ancient sacrifices and gatherings seem to take place
after the harvest as a sort of firstfruits, because it was at these seasons
that people had most leisure. All the communities, then, seem to be parts
of the political community; and the particular kinds friendship will correspond
to the particular kinds of community.
10
There are three kinds of constitution, and
an equal number of deviation-forms--perversions, as it were, of them. The
constitutions are monarchy, aristocracy, and thirdly that which is based
on a property qualification, which it seems appropriate to call timocratic,
though most people are wont to call it polity. The best of these is monarchy,
the worst timocracy. The deviation from monarchy is tyrany; for both are
forms of one-man rule, but there is the greatest difference between them;
the tyrant looks to his own advantage, the king to that of his subjects.
For a man is not a king unless he is sufficient to himself and excels his
subjects in all good things; and such a man needs nothing further; therefore
he will not look to his own interests but to those of his subjects; for
a king who is not like that would be a mere titular king. Now tyranny is
the very contrary of this; the tyrant pursues his own good. And it is clearer
in the case of tyranny that it is the worst deviation-form; but it is the
contrary of the best that is worst. Monarchy passes over into tyranny;
for tyranny is the evil form of one-man rule and the bad king becomes a
tyrant. Aristocracy passes over into oligarchy by the badness of the rulers,
who distribute contrary to equity what belongs to the city-all or most
of the good things to themselves, and office always to the same people,
paying most regard to wealth; thus the rulers are few and are bad men instead
of the most worthy. Timocracy passes over into democracy; for these are
coterminous, since it is the ideal even of timocracy to be the rule of
the majority, and all who have the property qualification count as equal.
Democracy is the least bad of the deviations; for in its case the form
of constitution is but a slight deviation. These then are the changes to
which constitutions are most subject; for these are the smallest and easiest
transitions.
One may find resemblances to the constitutions
and, as it were, patterns of them even in households. For the association
of a father with his sons bears the form of monarchy, since the father
cares for his children; and this is why Homer calls Zeus 'father'; it is
the ideal of monarchy to be paternal rule. But among the Persians the rule
of the father is tyrannical; they use their sons as slaves. Tyrannical
too is the rule of a master over slaves; for it is the advantage of the
master that is brought about in it. Now this seems to be a correct form
of government, but the Persian type is perverted; for the modes of rule
appropriate to different relations are diverse. The association of man
and wife seems to be aristocratic; for the man rules in accordance with
his worth, and in those matters in which a man should rule, but the matters
that befit a woman he hands over to her. If the man rules in everything
the relation passes over into oligarchy; for in doing so he is not acting
in accordance with their respective worth, and not ruling in virtue of
his superiority. Sometimes, however, women rule, because they are heiresses;
so their rule is not in virtue of excellence but due to wealth and power,
as in oligarchies. The association of brothers is like timocracy; for they
are equal, except in so far as they differ in age; hence if they differ
much in age, the friendship is no longer of the fraternal type. Democracy
is found chiefly in masterless dwellings (for here every one is on an equality),
and in those in which the ruler is weak and every one has licence to do
as he pleases.
11
Each of the constitutions may be seen to involve
friendship just in so far as it involves justice. The friendship between
a king and his subjects depends on an excess of benefits conferred; for
he confers benefits on his subjects if being a good man he cares for them
with a view to their well-being, as a shepherd does for his sheep (whence
Homer called Agamemnon 'shepherd of the peoples'). Such too is the friendship
of a father, though this exceeds the other in the greatness of the benefits
conferred; for he is responsible for the existence of his children, which
is thought the greatest good, and for their nurture and upbringing.
These things are ascribed to ancestors as
well. Further, by nature a father tends to rule over his sons, ancestors
over descendants, a king over his subjects. These friendships imply superiority
of one party over the other, which is why ancestors are honoured. The justice
therefore that exists between persons so related is not the same on both
sides but is in every case proportioned to merit; for that is true of the
friendship as well. The friendship of man and wife, again, is the same
that is found in an aristocracy; for it is in accordance with virtue the
better gets more of what is good, and each gets what befits him; and so,
too, with the justice in these relations. The friendship of brothers is
like that of comrades; for they are equal and of like age, and such persons
are for the most part like in their feelings and their character. Like
this, too, is the friendship appropriate to timocratic government; for
in such a constitution the ideal is for the citizens to be equal and fair;
therefore rule is taken in turn, and on equal terms; and the friendship
appropriate here will correspond.
But in the deviation-forms, as justice hardly
exists, so too does friendship. It exists least in the worst form; in tyranny
there is little or no friendship. For where there is nothing common to
ruler and ruled, there is not friendship either, since there is not justice;
e.g. between craftsman and tool, soul and body, master and slave; the latter
in each case is benefited by that which uses it, but there is no friendship
nor justice towards lifeless things. But neither is there friendship towards
a horse or an ox, nor to a slave qua slave. For there is nothing common
to the two parties; the slave is a living tool and the tool a lifeless
slave. Qua slave then, one cannot be friends with him. But qua man one
can; for there seems to be some justice between any man and any other who
can share in a system of law or be a party to an agreement; therefore there
can also be friendship with him in so far as he is a man. Therefore while
in tyrannies friendship and justice hardly exist, in democracies they exist
more fully; for where the citizens are equal they have much in common.
12
Every form of friendship, then, involves association,
as has been said. One might, however, mark off from the rest both the friendship
of kindred and that of comrades. Those of fellow-citizens, fellow-tribesmen,
fellow-voyagers, and the like are more like mere friendships of association;
for they seem to rest on a sort of compact. With them we might class the
friendship of host and guest. The friendship of kinsmen itself, while it
seems to be of many kinds, appears to depend in every case on parental
friendship; for parents love their children as being a part of themselves,
and children their parents as being something originating from them. Now
(1) arents know their offspring better than there children know that they
are their children, and (2) the originator feels his offspring to be his
own more than the offspring do their begetter; for the product belongs
to the producer (e.g. a tooth or hair or anything else to him whose it
is), but the producer does not belong to the product, or belongs in a less
degree. And (3) the length of time produces the same result; parents love
their children as soon as these are born, but children love their parents
only after time has elapsed and they have acquired understanding or the
power of discrimination by the senses. From these considerations it is
also plain why mothers love more than fathers do. Parents, then, love their
children as themselves (for their issue are by virtue of their separate
existence a sort of other selves), while children love their parents as
being born of them, and brothers love each other as being born of the same
parents; for their identity with them makes them identical with each other
(which is the reason why people talk of 'the same blood', 'the same stock',
and so on). They are, therefore, in a sense the same thing, though in separate
individuals. Two things that contribute greatly to friendship are a common
upbringing and similarity of age; for 'two of an age take to each other',
and people brought up together tend to be comrades; whence the friendship
of brothers is akin to that of comrades. And cousins and other kinsmen
are bound up together by derivation from brothers, viz. by being derived
from the same parents. They come to be closer together or farther apart
by virtue of the nearness or distance of the original ancestor.
The friendship of children to parents, and
of men to gods, is a relation to them as to something good and superior;
for they have conferred the greatest benefits, since they are the causes
of their being and of their nourishment, and of their education from their
birth; and this kind of friendship possesses pleasantness and utility also,
more than that of strangers, inasmuch as their life is lived more in common.
The friendship of brothers has the characteristics found in that of comrades
(and especially when these are good), and in general between people who
are like each other, inasmuch as they belong more to each other and start
with a love for each other from their very birth, and inasmuch as those
born of the same parents and brought up together and similarly educated
are more akin in character; and the test of time has been applied most
fully and convincingly in their case.
Between other kinsmen friendly relations are
found in due proportion. Between man and wife friendship seems to exist
by nature; for man is naturally inclined to form couples-even more than
to form cities, inasmuch as the household is earlier and more necessary
than the city, and reproduction is more common to man with the animals.
With the other animals the union extends only to this point, but human
beings live together not only for the sake of reproduction but also for
the various purposes of life; for from the start the functions are divided,
and those of man and woman are different; so they help each other by throwing
their peculiar gifts into the common stock. It is for these reasons that
both utility and pleasure seem to be found in this kind of friendship.
But this friendship may be based also on virtue, if the parties are good;
for each has its own virtue and they will delight in the fact. And children
seem to be a bond of union (which is the reason why childless people part
more easily); for children are a good common to both and what is common
holds them together.
How man and wife and in general friend
and friend ought mutually to behave seems to be the same question as how
it is just for them to behave; for a man does not seem to have the same
duties to a friend, a stranger, a comrade, and a schoolfellow.
13
There are three kinds of friendship, as we
said at the outset of our inquiry, and in respect of each some are friends
on an equality and others by virtue of a superiority (for not only can
equally good men become friends but a better man can make friends with
a worse, and similarly in friendships of pleasure or utility the friends
may be equal or unequal in the benefits they confer). This being so, equals
must effect the required equalization on a basis of equality in love and
in all other respects, while unequals must render what is in proportion
to their superiority or inferiority. Complaints and reproaches arise either
only or chiefly in the friendship of utility, and this is only to be expected.
For those who are friends on the ground of virtue are anxious to do well
by each other (since that is a mark of virtue and of friendship), and between
men who are emulating each other in this there cannot be complaints or
quarrels; no one is offended by a man who loves him and does well by him-if
he is a person of nice feeling he takes his revenge by doing well by the
other. And the man who excels the other in the services he renders will
not complain of his friend, since he gets what he aims at; for each man
desires what is good. Nor do complaints arise much even in friendships
of pleasure; for both get at the same time what they desire, if they enjoy
spending their time together; and even a man who complained of another
for not affording him pleasure would seem ridiculous, since it is in his
power not to spend his days with him.
But the friendship of utility is full of complaints;
for as they use each other for their own interests they always want to
get the better of the bargain, and think they have got less than they should,
and blame their partners because they do not get all they 'want and deserve';
and those who do well by others cannot help them as much as those whom
they benefit want.
Now it seems that, as justice is of two kinds,
one unwritten and the other legal, one kind of friendship of utility is
moral and the other legal. And so complaints arise most of all when men
do not dissolve the relation in the spirit of the same type of friendship
in which they contracted it. The legal type is that which is on fixed terms;
its purely commercial variety is on the basis of immediate payment, while
the more liberal variety allows time but stipulates for a definite quid
pro quo. In this variety the debt is clear and not ambiguous, but in the
postponement it contains an element of friendliness; and so some states
do not allow suits arising out of such agreements, but think men who have
bargained on a basis of credit ought to accept the consequences. The moral
type is not on fixed terms; it makes a gift, or does whatever it does,
as to a friend; but one expects to receive as much or more, as having not
given but lent; and if a man is worse off when the relation is dissolved
than he was when it was contracted he will complain. This happens because
all or most men, while they wish for what is noble, choose what is advantageous;
now it is noble to do well by another without a view to repayment, but
it is the receiving of benefits that is advantageous. Therefore if we can
we should return the equivalent of what we have received (for we must not
make a man our friend against his will; we must recognize that we were
mistaken at the first and took a benefit from a person we should not have
taken it from-since it was not from a friend, nor from one who did it just
for the sake of acting so-and we must settle up just as if we had been
benefited on fixed terms). Indeed, one would agree to repay if one could
(if one could not, even the giver would not have expected one to do so);
therefore if it is possible we must repay. But at the outset we must consider
the man by whom we are being benefited and on what terms he is acting,
in order that we may accept the benefit on these terms, or else decline
it.
It is disputable whether we ought to measure
a service by its utility to the receiver and make the return with a view
to that, or by the benevolence of the giver. For those who have received
say they have received from their benefactors what meant little to the
latter and what they might have got from others-minimizing the service;
while the givers, on the contrary, say it was the biggest thing they had,
and what could not have been got from others, and that it was given in
times of danger or similar need. Now if the friendship is one that aims
at utility, surely the advantage to the receiver is the measure. For it
is he that asks for the service, and the other man helps him on the assumption
that he will receive the equivalent; so the assistance has been precisely
as great as the advantage to the receiver, and therefore he must return
as much as he has received, or even more (for that would be nobler). In
friendships based on virtue on the other hand, complaints do not arise,
but the purpose of the doer is a sort of measure; for in purpose lies the
essential element of virtue and character.
14
Differences arise also in friendships based
on superiority; for each expects to get more out of them, but when this
happens the friendship is dissolved. Not only does the better man think
he ought to get more, since more should be assigned to a good man, but
the more useful similarly expects this; they say a useless man should not
get as much as they should, since it becomes an act of public service and
not a friendship if the proceeds of the friendship do not answer to the
worth of the benefits conferred. For they think that, as in a commercial
partnership those who put more in get more out, so it should be in friendship.
But the man who is in a state of need and inferiority makes the opposite
claim; they think it is the part of a good friend to help those who are
in need; what, they say, is the use of being the friend of a good man or
a powerful man, if one is to get nothing out of it?
At all events it seems that each party is
justified in his claim, and that each should get more out of the friendship
than the other-not more of the same thing, however, but the superior more
honour and the inferior more gain; for honour is the prize of virtue and
of beneficence, while gain is the assistance required by inferiority.
It seems to be so in constitutional arrangements
also; the man who contributes nothing good to the common stock is not honoured;
for what belongs to the public is given to the man who benefits the public,
and honour does belong to the public. It is not possible to get wealth
from the common stock and at the same time honour. For no one puts up with
the smaller share in all things; therefore to the man who loses in wealth
they assign honour and to the man who is willing to be paid, wealth, since
the proportion to merit equalizes the parties and preserves the friendship,
as we have said. This then is also the way in which we should associate
with unequals; the man who is benefited in respect of wealth or virtue
must give honour in return, repaying what he can. For friendship asks a
man to do what he can, not what is proportional to the merits of the case;
since that cannot always be done, e.g. in honours paid to the gods or to
parents; for no one could ever return to them the equivalent of what he
gets, but the man who serves them to the utmost of his power is thought
to be a good man. This is why it would not seem open to a man to disown
his father (though a father may disown his son); being in debt, he should
repay, but there is nothing by doing which a son will have done the equivalent
of what he has received, so that he is always in debt. But creditors can
remit a debt; and a father can therefore do so too. At the same time it
is thought that presumably no one would repudiate a son who was not far
gone in wickedness; for apart from the natural friendship of father and
son it is human nature not to reject a son's assistance. But the son, if
he is wicked, will naturally avoid aiding his father, or not be zealous
about it; for most people wish to get benefits, but avoid doing them, as
a thing unprofitable.-So much for these questions.
BOOK IX
1
IN all friendships between dissimilars it
is, as we have said, proportion that equalizes the parties and preserves
the friendship; e.g. in the political form of friendship the shoemaker
gets a return for his shoes in proportion to his worth, and the weaver
and all other craftsmen do the same. Now here a common measure has been
provided in the form of money, and therefore everything is referred to
this and measured by this; but in the friendship of lovers sometimes the
lover complains that his excess of love is not met by love in return though
perhaps there is nothing lovable about him), while often the beloved complains
that the lover who formerly promised everything now performs nothing. Such
incidents happen when the lover loves the beloved for the sake of pleasure
while the beloved loves the lover for the sake of utility, and they do
not both possess the qualities expected of them. If these be the objects
of the friendship it is dissolved when they do not get the things that
formed the motives of their love; for each did not love the other person
himself but the qualities he had, and these were not enduring; that is
why the friendships also are transient. But the love of characters, as
has been said, endures because it is self-dependent. Differences arise
when what they get is something different and not what they desire; for
it is like getting nothing at all when we do not get what we aim at; compare
the story of the person who made promises to a lyre-player, promising him
the more, the better he sang, but in the morning, when the other demanded
the fulfilment of his promises, said that he had given pleasure for pleasure.
Now if this had been what each wanted, all would have been well; but if
the one wanted enjoyment but the other gain, and the one has what he wants
while the other has not, the terms of the association will not have been
properly fulfilled; for what each in fact wants is what he attends to,
and it is for the sake of that that that he will give what he has.
But who is to fix the worth of the service;
he who makes the sacrifice or he who has got the advantage? At any rate
the other seems to leave it to him. This is what they say Protagoras used
to do; whenever he taught anything whatsoever, he bade the learner assess
the value of the knowledge, and accepted the amount so fixed. But in such
matters some men approve of the saying 'let a man have his fixed reward'.
Those who get the money first and then do none of the things they said
they would, owing to the extravagance of their promises, naturally find
themselves the objects of complaint; for they do not fulfil what they agreed
to. The sophists are perhaps compelled to do this because no one would
give money for the things they do know. These people then, if they do not
do what they have been paid for, are naturally made the objects of complaint.
But where there is no contract of service,
those who give up something for the sake of the other party cannot (as
we have said) be complained of (for that is the nature of the friendship
of virtue), and the return to them must be made on the basis of their purpose
(for it is purpose that is the characteristic thing in a friend and in
virtue). And so too, it seems, should one make a return to those with whom
one has studied philosophy; for their worth cannot be measured against
money, and they can get no honour which will balance their services, but
still it is perhaps enough, as it is with the gods and with one's parents,
to give them what one can.
If the gift was not of this sort, but was
made with a view to a return, it is no doubt preferable that the return
made should be one that seems fair to both parties, but if this cannot
be achieved, it would seem not only necessary that the person who gets
the first service should fix the reward, but also just; for if the other
gets in return the equivalent of the advantage the beneficiary has received,
or the price lie would have paid for the pleasure, he will have got what
is fair as from the other.
We see this happening too with things put
up for sale, and in some places there are laws providing that no actions
shall arise out of voluntary contracts, on the assumption that one should
settle with a person to whom one has given credit, in the spirit in which
one bargained with him. The law holds that it is more just that the person
to whom credit was given should fix the terms than that the person who
gave credit should do so. For most things are not assessed at the same
value by those who have them and those who want them; each class values
highly what is its own and what it is offering; yet the return is made
on the terms fixed by the receiver. But no doubt the receiver should assess
a thing not at what it seems worth when he has it, but at what he assessed
it at before he had it.
2
A further problem is set by such questions
as, whether one should in all things give the preference to one's father
and obey him, or whether when one is ill one should trust a doctor, and
when one has to elect a general should elect a man of military skill; and
similarly whether one should render a service by preference to a friend
or to a good man, and should show gratitude to a benefactor or oblige a
friend, if one cannot do both.
All such questions are hard, are they not,
to decide with precision? For they admit of many variations of all sorts
in respect both of the magnitude of the service and of its nobility necessity.
But that we should not give the preference in all things to the same person
is plain enough; and we must for the most part return benefits rather than
oblige friends, as we must pay back a loan to a creditor rather than make
one to a friend. But perhaps even this is not always true; e.g. should
a man who has been ransomed out of the hands of brigands ransom his ransomer
in return, whoever he may be (or pay him if he has not been captured but
demands payment) or should he ransom his father? It would seem that he
should ransom his father in preference even to himself. As we have said,
then, generally the debt should be paid, but if the gift is exceedingly
noble or exceedingly necessary, one should defer to these considerations.
For sometimes it is not even fair to return the equivalent of what one
has received, when the one man has done a service to one whom he knows
to be good, while the other makes a return to one whom he believes to be
bad. For that matter, one should sometimes not lend in return to one who
has lent to oneself; for the one person lent to a good man, expecting to
recover his loan, while the other has no hope of recovering from one who
is believed to be bad. Therefore if the facts really are so, the demand
is not fair; and if they are not, but people think they are, they would
be held to be doing nothing strange in refusing. As we have often pointed
out, then, discussions about feelings and actions have just as much definiteness
as their subject-matter.
That we should not make the same return to
every one, nor give a father the preference in everything, as one does
not sacrifice everything to Zeus, is plain enough; but since we ought to
render different things to parents, brothers, comrades, and benefactors,
we ought to render to each class what is appropriate and becoming. And
this is what people seem in fact to do; to marriages they invite their
kinsfolk; for these have a part in the family and therefore in the doings
that affect the family; and at funerals also they think that kinsfolk,
before all others, should meet, for the same reason. And it would be thought
that in the matter of food we should help our parents before all others,
since we owe our own nourishment to them, and it is more honourable to
help in this respect the authors of our being even before ourselves; and
honour too one should give to one's parents as one does to the gods, but
not any and every honour; for that matter one should not give the same
honour to one's father and one's mother, nor again should one give them
the honour due to a philosopher or to a general, but the honour due to
a father, or again to a mother. To all older persons, too, one should give
honour appropriate to their age, by rising to receive them and finding
seats for them and so on; while to comrades and brothers one should allow
freedom of speech and common use of all things. To kinsmen, too, and fellow-tribesmen
and fellow-citizens and to every other class one should always try to assign
what is appropriate, and to compare the claims of each class with respect
to nearness of relation and to virtue or usefulness. The comparison is
easier when the persons belong to the same class, and more laborious when
they are different. Yet we must not on that account shrink from the task,
but decide the question as best we can.
3
Another question that arises is whether friendships
should or should not be broken off when the other party does not remain
the same. Perhaps we may say that there is nothing strange in breaking
off a friendship based on utility or pleasure, when our friends no longer
have these attributes. For it was of these attributes that we were the
friends; and when these have failed it is reasonable to love no longer.
But one might complain of another if, when he loved us for our usefulness
or pleasantness, he pretended to love us for our character. For, as we
said at the outset, most differences arise between friends when they are
not friends in the spirit in which they think they are. So when a man has
deceived himself and has thought he was being loved for his character,
when the other person was doing nothing of the kind, he must blame himself;
when he has been deceived by the pretences of the other person, it is just
that he should complain against his deceiver; he will complain with more
justice than one does against people who counterfeit the currency, inasmuch
as the wrongdoing is concerned with something more valuable.
But if one accepts another man as good, and
he turns out badly and is seen to do so, must one still love him? Surely
it is impossible, since not everything can be loved, but only what is good.
What is evil neither can nor should be loved; for it is not one's duty
to be a lover of evil, nor to become like what is bad; and we have said
that like is dear like. Must the friendship, then, be forthwith broken
off? Or is this not so in all cases, but only when one's friends are incurable
in their wickedness? If they are capable of being reformed one should rather
come to the assistance of their character or their property, inasmuch as
this is better and more characteristic of friendship. But a man who breaks
off such a friendship would seem to be doing nothing strange; for it was
not to a man of this sort that he was a friend; when his friend has changed,
therefore, and he is unable to save him, he gives him up.
But if one friend remained the same while
the other became better and far outstripped him in virtue, should the latter
treat the former as a friend? Surely he cannot. When the interval is great
this becomes most plain, e.g. in the case of childish friendships; if one
friend remained a child in intellect while the other became a fully developed
man, how could they be friends when they neither approved of the same things
nor delighted in and were pained by the same things? For not even with
regard to each other will their tastes agree, and without this (as we saw)
they cannot be friends; for they cannot live together. But we have discussed
these matters.
Should he, then, behave no otherwise towards
him than he would if he had never been his friend? Surely he should keep
a remembrance of their former intimacy, and as we think we ought to oblige
friends rather than strangers, so to those who have been our friends we
ought to make some allowance for our former friendship, when the breach
has not been due to excess of wickedness.
4
Friendly relations with one's
neighbours, and the marks by which friendships are defined, seem to have
proceeded from a man's relations to himself. For (1) we define a friend
as one who wishes and does what is good, or seems so, for the sake of his
friend, or (2) as one who wishes his friend to exist and live, for his
sake; which mothers do to their children, and friends do who have come
into conflict. And (3) others define him as one who lives with and (4)
has the same tastes as another, or (5) one who grieves and rejoices with
his friend; and this too is found in mothers most of all. It is by some
one of these characterstics that friendship too is defined.
Now each of these is true of the good man's
relation to himself (and of all other men in so far as they think themselves
good; virtue and the good man seem, as has been said, to be the measure
of every class of things). For his opinions are harmonious, and he desires
the same things with all his soul; and therefore he wishes for himself
what is good and what seems so, and does it (for it is characteristic of
the good man to work out the good), and does so for his own sake (for he
does it for the sake of the intellectual element in him, which is thought
to be the man himself); and he wishes himself to live and be preserved,
and especially the element by virtue of which he thinks. For existence
is good to the virtuous man, and each man wishes himself what is good,
while no one chooses to possess the whole world if he has first to become
some one else (for that matter, even now God possesses the good); he wishes
for this only on condition of being whatever he is; and the element that
thinks would seem to be the individual man, or to be so more than any other
element in him. And such a man wishes to live with himself; for he does
so with pleasure, since the memories of his past acts are delightful and
his hopes for the future are good, and therefore pleasant. His mind is
well stored too with subjects of contemplation. And he grieves and rejoices,
more than any other, with himself; for the same thing is always painful,
and the same thing always pleasant, and not one thing at one time and another
at another; he has, so to speak, nothing to repent of.
Therefore, since each of these characteristics
belongs to the good man in relation to himself, and he is related to his
friend as to himself (for his friend is another self), friendship too is
thought to be one of these attributes, and those who have these attributes
to be friends. Whether there is or is not friendship between a man and
himself is a question we may dismiss for the present; there would seem
to be friendship in so far as he is two or more, to judge from the afore-mentioned
attributes of friendship, and from the fact that the extreme of friendship
is likened to one's love for oneself.
But the attributes named seem to belong even
to the majority of men, poor creatures though they may be. Are we to say
then that in so far as they are satisfied with themselves and think they
are good, they share in these attributes? Certainly no one who is thoroughly
bad and impious has these attributes, or even seems to do so. They hardly
belong even to inferior people; for they are at variance with themselves,
and have appetites for some things and rational desires for others. This
is true, for instance, of incontinent people; for they choose, instead
of the things they themselves think good, things that are pleasant but
hurtful; while others again, through cowardice and laziness, shrink from
doing what they think best for themselves. And those who have done many
terrible deeds and are hated for their wickedness even shrink from life
and destroy themselves. And wicked men seek for people with whom to spend
their days, and shun themselves; for they remember many a grevious deed,
and anticipate others like them, when they are by themselves, but when
they are with others they forget. And having nothing lovable in them they
have no feeling of love to themselves. Therefore also such men do not rejoice
or grieve with themselves; for their soul is rent by faction, and one element
in it by reason of its wickedness grieves when it abstains from certain
acts, while the other part is pleased, and one draws them this way and
the other that, as if they were pulling them in pieces. If a man cannot
at the same time be pained and pleased, at all events after a short time
he is pained because he was pleased, and he could have wished that these
things had not been pleasant to him; for bad men are laden with repentance.
Therefore the bad man does not seem to be
amicably disposed even to himself, because there is nothing in him to love;
so that if to be thus is the height of wretchedness, we should strain every
nerve to avoid wickedness and should endeavour to be good; for so and only
so can one be either friendly to oneself or a friend to another.
5
Goodwill is a friendly sort of relation, but
is not identical with friendship; for one may have goodwill both towards
people whom one does not know, and without their knowing it, but not friendship.
This has indeed been said already.' But goodwill is not even friendly feeling.
For it does not involve intensity or desire, whereas these accompany friendly
feeling; and friendly feeling implies intimacy while goodwill may arise
of a sudden, as it does towards competitors in a contest; we come to feel
goodwill for them and to share in their wishes, but we would not do anything
with them; for, as we said, we feel goodwill suddenly and love them only
superficially.
Goodwill seems, then, to be a beginning of
friendship, as the pleasure of the eye is the beginning of love. For no
one loves if he has not first been delighted by the form of the beloved,
but he who delights in the form of another does not, for all that, love
him, but only does so when he also longs for him when absent and craves
for his presence; so too it is not possible for people to be friends if
they have not come to feel goodwill for each other, but those who feel
goodwill are not for all that friends; for they only wish well to those
for whom they feel goodwill, and would not do anything with them nor take
trouble for them. And so one might by an extension of the term friendship
say that goodwill is inactive friendship, though when it is prolonged and
reaches the point of intimacy it becomes friendship-not the friendship
based on utility nor that based on pleasure; for goodwill too does not
arise on those terms. The man who has received a benefit bestows goodwill
in return for what has been done to him, but in doing so is only doing
what is just; while he who wishes some one to prosper because he hopes
for enrichment through him seems to have goodwill not to him but rather
to himself, just as a man is not a friend to another if he cherishes him
for the sake of some use to be made of him. In general, goodwill arises
on account of some excellence and worth, when one man seems to another
beautiful or brave or something of the sort, as we pointed out in the case
of competitors in a contest.
6
Unanimity also seems to be a friendly relation.
For this reason it is not identity of opinion; for that might occur even
with people who do not know each other; nor do we say that people who have
the same views on any and every subject are unanimous, e.g. those who agree
about the heavenly bodies (for unanimity about these is not a friendly
relation), but we do say that a city is unanimous when men have the same
opinion about what is to their interest, and choose the same actions, and
do what they have resolved in common. It is about things to be done, therefore,
that people are said to be unanimous, and, among these, about matters of
consequence and in which it is possible for both or all parties to get
what they want; e.g. a city is unanimous when all its citizens think that
the offices in it should be elective, or that they should form an alliance
with Sparta, or that Pittacus should be their ruler-at a time when he himself
was also willing to rule. But when each of two people wishes himself to
have the thing in question, like the captains in the Phoenissae, they are
in a state of faction; for it is not unanimity when each of two parties
thinks of the same thing, whatever that may be, but only when they think
of the same thing in the same hands, e.g. when both the common people and
those of the better class wish the best men to rule; for thus and thus
alone do all get what they aim at. Unanimity seems, then, to be political
friendship, as indeed it is commonly said to be; for it is concerned with
things that are to our interest and have an influence on our life.
Now such unanimity is found among good men;
for they are unanimous both in themselves and with one another, being,
so to say, of one mind (for the wishes of such men are constant and not
at the mercy of opposing currents like a strait of the sea), and they wish
for what is just and what is advantageous, and these are the objects of
their common endeavour as well. But bad men cannot be unanimous except
to a small extent, any more than they can be friends, since they aim at
getting more than their share of advantages, while in labour and public
service they fall short of their share; and each man wishing for advantage
to himself criticizes his neighbour and stands in his way; for if people
do not watch it carefully the common weal is soon destroyed. The result
is that they are in a state of faction, putting compulsion on each other
but unwilling themselves to do what is just.
7
Benefactors are thought to love those they
have benefited, more than those who have been well treated love those that
have treated them well, and this is discussed as though it were paradoxical.
Most people think it is because the latter are in the position of debtors
and the former of creditors; and therefore as, in the case of loans, debtors
wish their creditors did not exist, while creditors actually take care
of the safety of their debtors, so it is thought that benefactors wish
the objects of their action to exist since they will then get their gratitude,
while the beneficiaries take no interest in making this return. Epicharmus
would perhaps declare that they say this because they 'look at things on
their bad side', but it is quite like human nature; for most people are
forgetful, and are more anxious to be well treated than to treat others
well. But the cause would seem to be more deeply rooted in the nature of
things; the case of those who have lent money is not even analogous. For
they have no friendly feeling to their debtors, but only a wish that they
may kept safe with a view to what is to be got from them; while those who
have done a service to others feel friendship and love for those they have
served even if these are not of any use to them and never will be. This
is what happens with craftsmen too; every man loves his own handiwork better
than he would be loved by it if it came alive; and this happens perhaps
most of all with poets; for they have an excessive love for their own poems,
doting on them as if they were their children. This is what the position
of benefactors is like; for that which they have treated well is their
handiwork, and therefore they love this more than the handiwork does its
maker. The cause of this is that existence is to all men a thing to be
chosen and loved, and that we exist by virtue of activity (i.e. by living
and acting), and that the handiwork is in a sense, the producer in activity;
he loves his handiwork, therefore, because he loves existence. And this
is rooted in the nature of things; for what he is in potentiality, his
handiwork manifests in activity.
At the same time to the benefactor that is
noble which depends on his action, so that he delights in the object of
his action, whereas to the patient there is nothing noble in the agent,
but at most something advantageous, and this is less pleasant and lovable.
What is pleasant is the activity of the present, the hope of the future,
the memory of the past; but most pleasant is that which depends on activity,
and similarly this is most lovable. Now for a man who has made something
his work remains (for the noble is lasting), but for the person acted on
the utility passes away. And the memory of noble things is pleasant, but
that of useful things is not likely to be pleasant, or is less so; though
the reverse seems true of expectation.
Further, love is like activity, being loved
like passivity; and loving and its concomitants are attributes of those
who are the more active.
Again, all men love more what they have won
by labour; e.g. those who have made their money love it more than those
who have inherited it; and to be well treated seems to involve no labour,
while to treat others well is a laborious task. These are the reasons,
too, why mothers are fonder of their children than fathers; bringing them
into the world costs them more pains, and they know better that the children
are their own. This last point, too, would seem to apply to benefactors.
8
The question is also debated, whether a man
should love himself most, or some one else. People criticize those who
love themselves most, and call them self-lovers, using this as an epithet
of disgrace, and a bad man seems to do everything for his own sake, and
the more so the more wicked he is-and so men reproach him, for instance,
with doing nothing of his own accord-while the good man acts for honour's
sake, and the more so the better he is, and acts for his friend's sake,
and sacrifices his own interest.
But the facts clash with these arguments,
and this is not surprising. For men say that one ought to love best one's
best friend, and man's best friend is one who wishes well to the object
of his wish for his sake, even if no one is to know of it; and these attributes
are found most of all in a man's attitude towards himself, and so are all
the other attributes by which a friend is defined; for, as we have said,
it is from this relation that all the characteristics of friendship have
extended to our neighbours. All the proverbs, too, agree with this, e.g.
'a single soul', and 'what friends have is common property', and 'friendship
is equality', and 'charity begins at home'; for all these marks will be
found most in a man's relation to himself; he is his own best friend and
therefore ought to love himself best. It is therefore a reasonable question,
which of the two views we should follow; for both are plausible.
Perhaps we ought to mark off such arguments
from each other and determine how far and in what respects each view is
right. Now if we grasp the sense in which each school uses the phrase 'lover
of self', the truth may become evident. Those who use the term as one of
reproach ascribe self-love to people who assign to themselves the greater
share of wealth, honours, and bodily pleasures; for these are what most
people desire, and busy themselves about as though they were the best of
all things, which is the reason, too, why they become objects of competition.
So those who are grasping with regard to these things gratify their appetites
and in general their feelings and the irrational element of the soul; and
most men are of this nature (which is the reason why the epithet has come
to be used as it is-it takes its meaning from the prevailing type of self-love,
which is a bad one); it is just, therefore, that men who are lovers of
self in this way are reproached for being so. That it is those who give
themselves the preference in regard to objects of this sort that most people
usually call lovers of self is plain; for if a man were always anxious
that he himself, above all things, should act justly, temperately, or in
accordance with any other of the virtues, and in general were always to
try to secure for himself the honourable course, no one will call such
a man a lover of self or blame him.
But such a man would seem more than the other
a lover of self; at all events he assigns to himself the things that are
noblest and best, and gratifies the most authoritative element in and in
all things obeys this; and just as a city or any other systematic whole
is most properly identified with the most authoritative element in it,
so is a man; and therefore the man who loves this and gratifies it is most
of all a lover of self. Besides, a man is said to have or not to have self-control
according as his reason has or has not the control, on the assumption that
this is the man himself; and the things men have done on a rational principle
are thought most properly their own acts and voluntary acts. That this
is the man himself, then, or is so more than anything else, is plain, and
also that the good man loves most this part of him. Whence it follows that
he is most truly a lover of self, of another type than that which is a
matter of reproach, and as different from that as living according to a
rational principle is from living as passion dictates, and desiring what
is noble from desiring what seems advantageous. Those, then, who busy themselves
in an exceptional degree with noble actions all men approve and praise;
and if all were to strive towards what is noble and strain every nerve
to do the noblest deeds, everything would be as it should be for the common
weal, and every one would secure for himself the goods that are greatest,
since virtue is the greatest of goods.
Therefore the good man should be a lover of
self (for he will both himself profit by doing noble acts, and will benefit
his fellows), but the wicked man should not; for he will hurt both himself
and his neighbours, following as he does evil passions. For the wicked
man, what he does clashes with what he ought to do, but what the good man
ought to do he does; for reason in each of its possessors chooses what
is best for itself, and the good man obeys his reason. It is true of the
good man too that he does many acts for the sake of his friends and his
country, and if necessary dies for them; for he will throw away both wealth
and honours and in general the goods that are objects of competition, gaining
for himself nobility; since he would prefer a short period of intense pleasure
to a long one of mild enjoyment, a twelvemonth of noble life to many years
of humdrum existence, and one great and noble action to many trivial ones.
Now those who die for others doubtless attain this result; it is therefore
a great prize that they choose for themselves. They will throw away wealth
too on condition that their friends will gain more; for while a man's friend
gains wealth he himself achieves nobility; he is therefore assigning the
greater good to himself. The same too is true of honour and office; all
these things he will sacrifice to his friend; for this is noble and laudable
for himself. Rightly then is he thought to be good, since he chooses nobility
before all else. But he may even give up actions to his friend; it may
be nobler to become the cause of his friend's acting than to act himself.
In all the actions, therefore, that men are praised for, the good man is
seen to assign to himself the greater share in what is noble. In this sense,
then, as has been said, a man should be a lover of self; but in the sense
in which most men are so, he ought not.
9
It is also disputed whether the happy man
will need friends or not. It is said that those who are supremely happy
and self-sufficient have no need of friends; for they have the things that
are good, and therefore being self-sufficient they need nothing further,
while a friend, being another self, furnishes what a man cannot provide
by his own effort; whence the saying 'when fortune is kind, what need of
friends?' But it seems strange, when one assigns all good things to the
happy man, not to assign friends, who are thought the greatest of external
goods. And if it is more characteristic of a friend to do well by another
than to be well done by, and to confer benefits is characteristic of the
good man and of virtue, and it is nobler to do well by friends than by
strangers, the good man will need people to do well by. This is why the
question is asked whether we need friends more in prosperity or in adversity,
on the assumption that not only does a man in adversity need people to
confer benefits on him, but also those who are prospering need people to
do well by. Surely it is strange, too, to make the supremely happy man
a solitary; for no one would choose the whole world on condition of being
alone, since man is a political creature and one whose nature is to live
with others. Therefore even the happy man lives with others; for he has
the things that are by nature good. And plainly it is better to spend his
days with friends and good men than with strangers or any chance persons.
Therefore the happy man needs friends.
What then is it that the first school means,
and in what respect is it right? Is it that most identify friends with
useful people? Of such friends indeed the supremely happy man will have
no need, since he already has the things that are good; nor will he need
those whom one makes one's friends because of their pleasantness, or he
will need them only to a small extent (for his life, being pleasant, has
no need of adventitious pleasure); and because he does not need such friends
he is thought not to need friends.
But that is surely not true. For we have said
at the outset that happiness is an activity; and activity plainly comes
into being and is not present at the start like a piece of property. If
(1) happiness lies in living and being active, and the good man's activity
is virtuous and pleasant in itself, as we have said at the outset, and
(2) a thing's being one's own is one of the attributes that make it pleasant,
and (3) we can contemplate our neighbours better than ourselves and their
actions better than our own, and if the actions of virtuous men who are
their friends are pleasant to good men (since these have both the attributes
that are naturally pleasant),-if this be so, the supremely happy man will
need friends of this sort, since his purpose is to contemplate worthy actions
and actions that are his own, and the actions of a good man who is his
friend have both these qualities.
Further, men think that the happy man ought
to live pleasantly. Now if he were a solitary, life would be hard for him;
for by oneself it is not easy to be continuously active; but with others
and towards others it is easier. With others therefore his activity will
be more continuous, and it is in itself pleasant, as it ought to be for
the man who is supremely happy; for a good man qua good delights in virtuous
actions and is vexed at vicious ones, as a musical man enjoys beautiful
tunes but is pained at bad ones. A certain training in virtue arises also
from the company of the good, as Theognis has said before us.
If we look deeper into the nature of things,
a virtuous friend seems to be naturally desirable for a virtuous man. For
that which is good by nature, we have said, is for the virtuous man good
and pleasant in itself. Now life is defined in the case of animals by the
power of perception in that of man by the power of perception or thought;
and a power is defined by reference to the corresponding activity, which
is the essential thing; therefore life seems to be essentially the act
of perceiving or thinking. And life is among the things that are good and
pleasant in themselves, since it is determinate and the determinate is
of the nature of the good; and that which is good by nature is also good
for the virtuous man (which is the reason why life seems pleasant to all
men); but we must not apply this to a wicked and corrupt life nor to a
life spent in pain; for such a life is indeterminate, as are its attributes.
The nature of pain will become plainer in what follows. But if life itself
is good and pleasant (which it seems to be, from the very fact that all
men desire it, and particularly those who are good and supremely happy;
for to such men life is most desirable, and their existence is the most
supremely happy) and if he who sees perceives that he sees, and he who
hears, that he hears, and he who walks, that he walks, and in the case
of all other activities similarly there is something which perceives that
we are active, so that if we perceive, we perceive that we perceive, and
if we think, that we think; and if to perceive that we perceive or think
is to perceive that we exist (for existence was defined as perceiving or
thinking); and if perceiving that one lives is in itself one of the things
that are pleasant (for life is by nature good, and to perceive what is
good present in oneself is pleasant); and if life is desirable, and particularly
so for good men, because to them existence is good and pleasant for they
are pleased at the consciousness of the presence in them of what is in
itself good); and if as the virtuous man is to himself, he is to his friend
also (for his friend is another self):-if all this be true, as his own
being is desirable for each man, so, or almost so, is that of his friend.
Now his being was seen to be desirable because he perceived his own goodness,
and such perception is pleasant in itself. He needs, therefore, to be conscious
of the existence of his friend as well, and this will be realized in their
living together and sharing in discussion and thought; for this is what
living together would seem to mean in the case of man, and not, as in the
case of cattle, feeding in the same place.
If, then, being is in itself desirable for
the supremely happy man (since it is by its nature good and pleasant),
and that of his friend is very much the same, a friend will be one of the
things that are desirable. Now that which is desirable for him he must
have, or he will be deficient in this respect. The man who is to be happy
will therefore need virtuous friends.
10
Should we, then, make as many friends as possible,
or-as in the case of hospitality it is thought to be suitable advice, that
one should be 'neither a man of many guests nor a man with none'-will that
apply to friendship as well; should a man neither be friendless nor have
an excessive number of friends?
To friends made with a view to utility this
saying would seem thoroughly applicable; for to do services to many people
in return is a laborious task and life is not long enough for its performance.
Therefore friends in excess of those who are sufficient for our own life
are superfluous, and hindrances to the noble life; so that we have no need
of them. Of friends made with a view to pleasure, also, few are enough,
as a little seasoning in food is enough.
But as regards good friends, should we have
as many as possible, or is there a limit to the number of one's friends,
as there is to the size of a city? You cannot make a city of ten men, and
if there are a hundred thousand it is a city no longer. But the proper
number is presumably not a single number, but anything that falls between
certain fixed points. So for friends too there is a fixed number perhaps
the largest number with whom one can live together (for that, we found,
thought to be very characteristic of friendship); and that one cannot live
with many people and divide oneself up among them is plain. Further, they
too must be friends of one another, if they are all to spend their days
together; and it is a hard business for this condition to be fulfilled
with a large number. It is found difficult, too, to rejoice and to grieve
in an intimate way with many people, for it may likely happen that one
has at once to be happy with one friend and to mourn with another. Presumably,
then, it is well not to seek to have as many friends as possible, but as
many as are enough for the purpose of living together; for it would seem
actually impossible to be a great friend to many people. This is why one
cannot love several people; love is ideally a sort of excess of friendship,
and that can only be felt towards one person; therefore great friendship
too can only be felt towards a few people. This seems to be confirmed in
practice; for we do not find many people who are friends in the comradely
way of friendship, and the famous friendships of this sort are always between
two people. Those who have many friends and mix intimately with them all
are thought to be no one's friend, except in the way proper to fellow-citizens,
and such people are also called obsequious. In the way proper to fellow-citizens,
indeed, it is possible to be the friend of many and yet not be obsequious
but a genuinely good man; but one cannot have with many people the friendship
based on virtue and on the character of our friends themselves, and we
must be content if we find even a few such.
11
Do we need friends more in good fortune or
in bad? They are sought after in both; for while men in adversity need
help, in prosperity they need people to live with and to make the objects
of their beneficence; for they wish to do well by others. Friendship, then,
is more necessary in bad fortune, and so it is useful friends that one
wants in this case; but it is more noble in good fortune, and so we also
seek for good men as our friends, since it is more desirable to confer
benefits on these and to live with these. For the very presence of friends
is pleasant both in good fortune and also in bad, since grief is lightened
when friends sorrow with us. Hence one might ask whether they share as
it were our burden, or-without that happening-their presence by its pleasantness,
and the thought of their grieving with us, make our pain less. Whether
it is for these reasons or for some other that our grief is lightened,
is a question that may be dismissed; at all events what we have described
appears to take place.
But their presence seems to contain a mixture
of various factors. The very seeing of one's friends is pleasant, especially
if one is in adversity, and becomes a safeguard against grief (for a friend
tends to comfort us both by the sight of him and by his words, if he is
tactful, since he knows our character and the things that please or pain
us); but to see him pained at our misfortunes is painful; for every one
shuns being a cause of pain to his friends. For this reason people of a
manly nature guard against making their friends grieve with them, and,
unless he be exceptionally insensible to pain, such a man cannot stand
the pain that ensues for his friends, and in general does not admit fellow-mourners
because he is not himself given to mourning; but women and womanly men
enjoy sympathisers in their grief, and love them as friends and companions
in sorrow. But in all things one obviously ought to imitate the better
type of person.
On the other hand, the presence of friends
in our prosperity implies both a pleasant passing of our time and the pleasant
thought of their pleasure at our own good fortune. For this cause it would
seem that we ought to summon our friends readily to share our good fortunes
(for the beneficent character is a noble one), but summon them to our bad
fortunes with hesitation; for we ought to give them as little a share as
possible in our evils whence the saying 'enough is my misfortune'. We should
summon friends to us most of all when they are likely by suffering a few
inconveniences to do us a great service.
Conversely, it is fitting to go unasked and
readily to the aid of those in adversity (for it is characteristic of a
friend to render services, and especially to those who are in need and
have not demanded them; such action is nobler and pleasanter for both persons);
but when our friends are prosperous we should join readily in their activities
(for they need friends for these too), but be tardy in coming forward to
be the objects of their kindness; for it is not noble to be keen to receive
benefits. Still, we must no doubt avoid getting the reputation of kill-joys
by repulsing them; for that sometimes happens.
The presence of friends, then, seems desirable
in all circumstances.
12
Does it not follow, then, that, as for lovers
the sight of the beloved is the thing they love most, and they prefer this
sense to the others because on it love depends most for its being and for
its origin, so for friends the most desirable thing is living together?
For friendship is a partnership, and as a man is to himself, so is he to
his friend; now in his own case the consciousness of his being is desirable,
and so therefore is the consciousness of his friend's being, and the activity
of this consciousness is produced when they live together, so that it is
natural that they aim at this. And whatever existence means for each class
of men, whatever it is for whose sake they value life, in that they wish
to occupy themselves with their friends; and so some drink together, others
dice together, others join in athletic exercises and hunting, or in the
study of philosophy, each class spending their days together in whatever
they love most in life; for since they wish to live with their friends,
they do and share in those things which give them the sense of living together.
Thus the friendship of bad men turns out an evil thing (for because of
their instability they unite in bad pursuits, and besides they become evil
by becoming like each other), while the friendship of good men is good,
being augmented by their companionship; and they are thought to become
better too by their activities and by improving each other; for from each
other they take the mould of the characteristics they approve-whence the
saying 'noble deeds from noble men'.-So much, then, for friendship; our
next task must be to discuss pleasure.
![]() |
Email
David H. Calhoun
Back to PHIL 401/501 Ancient Philosophy Page Back to David H. Calhoun's Home Page Copyright © 1998-99 by David Calhoun. All rights
reserved.
|