You will find in Plato’s Phaedrus a story about Thamus, the
king of a
great city of Upper
Egypt. For people such as ourselves,
who are inclined (in
Thoreau’s phrase) to be
tools of our tools, few legends are more instructive
than his. The story, as Socrates tells it to his
friend Phaedrus, unfolds in
the following way: Thamus once entertained the god Theuth, who
was the
inventor of many things,
including number, calculation, geometry, astronomy,
and writing. Theuth exhibited his inventions to King
Thamus, claiming that
they should be made widely
known and available to Egyptians.
Socrates
continues:
Thamus inquired into the use of each of them, and as Theuth
went through
them expressed approval or
disapproval, according as he judged Theuth’s
claims to be well or ill
founded. It would take too long to go
through all
that Thamus is reported to
have said for and against each of Theuth’s
inventions. But when it came to writing, Theuth
declared, “Here is an
accomplishment, my lord the
King, which will improve both the wisdom
and the memory of the
Egyptians. I have discovered a sure
receipt for
memory and wisdom.” To this, Thamus replied, “Theuth,, my
paragon of
inventors, the discoverer of
an art is not the best judge of the good or harm
which will accrue to those
who practice it. So it is in this; you,
who are the
father of writing, have out
of fondness for your off-spring attributed to it
quite the opposite of its
real function. Those who acquire it
will cease to
exercise their memory and
become forgetful; they will rely on writing to
bring thins to their
remembrance by external signs instead of by their own
internal resources. What you have discovered is a receipt for
recollection,
not for memory. And as for wisdom, your pupils will have the
reputations
for it without the
reality: they will receive a quantity
of information without
proper instructions, and in
consequence be thought very knowledgeable when
they are for the most part
quite ignorant. And because they are
filled with the
conceit of wisdom instead of
real wisdom they will be a burden to society.”
I begin my book with this
legend because in Thamus’ response there are several
sound principles from wich
we may begin to learn how to think with wise
circumspection about a
technological society. In fact, there
is even one error
in the judgment of Thamus,
from which we may also learn something of
importance. The error is not in his claim that writing
will damage memory and
create false wisdom. It is demonstrable that writing has had such
an effect.
Thamus’ error is in his
believing that writing will be a burden to society and
nothing but a burden. For all his wisdom, he fails to imagine what
writing’s
benefits might be, which, as
we know, have been considerable. We may
learn
from this that it is a
mistake to suppose that any technological innovation has
a one-sided effect. Every technology is both a burden and a
blessing; not
either-or, but
this-and-that. Nothing could be more
obvious, of course,
especially to those who have
given more than two minutes of thought to the
matter. Nonetheless, we are currently surrounded by
throngs of zealous
Theuths, one-eyed prophets
who see only what new technologies can do and are
incapable of imagining what
they will undo. We might call such
people
Technophiles. They gaze on technology as a lover does on
his beloved, seeing
it as without blemish and
entertaining no apprehension for the future.
They
are therefore dangerous and
are to be approached cautiously. On the
other
hand, some one-eyed
prophets, such as I (or so I am accused), are inclined to
speak only of burdens (in
the manner of Thamus) and are silent about the
opportunities that new
technologies make possible. The
Technophiles must speak
for themselves, and do so
all over the place. My defense is that
a dissenting
voice is sometimes needed to
moderate the din made by the enthusiastic
multitudes. If one is to err, it is better to err on the
side of Thamusian
skepticism. But it is an error nonetheless. And I might note that, with the
exceptions of his judgment
on writing, Thamus does not repeat this error.
You
might notice on rereading
the legend that he gives arguments for and against
each of Theuth’s
inventions. For it is inescapable that
every culture must
negotiate with technology,
whether it does so intelligently or not.
A bargain
is struck in which
technology giveth and technology taketh away.
The wise know
this well, and are rarely
impressed by dramatic technological changes, and
never overjoyed. Here, for example, is Freud on the matter,
from his doleful
Civilization and Its
Discontents:
One would like to ask:
is there, then no positive gain in pleasure, no
unequivocal increase in my
feeling on happiness, if I can, as often as
I please, hear the voice of
a child of mine who is living hundreds of
miles away or if I can learn
in the shortest possible time after a friend
has reached his destination
that he has come through the long and
difficult voyages
unharmed? Does it mean nothing that
medicine has
succeeded in enormously
reducing infant mortality and the danger of
infection for women in
childbirth, and, indeed, in considerably
lengthening the average life
of a civilized man?
Freud knew full well that
technical and scientific advances are not to be taken
lightly, which is why he
begins this passage by acknowledging them.
But he
ends it by reminding us of
what they have undone:
If there had been no railway to conquer distances, my child
would
never have left his native
town and I should need no telephone to
hear his voice; if traveling
across the ocean by ship had not been
introduced, my friend would
not have embarked on his sea-voyage
and I should not need a
cable to relieve my anxiety about him.
What
is the use of reducing
infantile mortality when it is precisely that
reduction which imposes the
greatest restraint on us in the begetting
of children, so that, taken
all round, we nevertheless rear no more
children than in the days
before the reign of hygiene, while at the
same time we have created
difficult conditions for our sexual life in
marriage…And, finally, what
good to us is a long life if it is difficult
and barren of joys, and if
it is so full of misery that we can only
welcome death as a
deliverer?
In tabulating the cost of technological progress, Freud takes a
rather
depressing line, that of a
man who agrees with Thoreau’s remark that our
inventions are but improved
means to an unimproved end. The
Technophile would
surely answer Freud by
saying that life has always been barren of joys and full
of misery but that the
telephone, ocean liners, and especially the reign of
hygiene have not only lengthened
life but made it a more agreeable
proposition. That is certainly an argument I would make
(thus proving I am no
one-eyed Technophobe), but
it is not necessary at this point to pursue it. I
have brought Freud into the
conversation only to show that a wise man—even one
of such a woeful
countenance—must begin his critique of technology by
acknowledging its
successes. Had King Thamus been as wise
as reputed, he would
not have forgotten to
include in his judgment a prophecy about the powers that
writing would enlarge. There is a calculus of technological change
that
requires a measure of
even-handedness.
So much for Thamus’ error of omission. There is another omission
worthy of note, but it is no
error. Thamus simply takes it for
granted—and
therefore does not feel it
necessary to say—that writing is not a neutral
technology whose good or
harm depends on the uses made of it. He
knows that
the uses made of any
technology are largely determined by the structure of the
technology itself—that is,
that its functions follow from its form.
This is
why Thamus is concerned not
with what people will write; he is concerned that
people will write. It is absurd to imagine Thamus advising, in
the manner of
today’s standard-brand
Technophiles, that, if only writing would be used for
the production of certain
kinds of texts and not others (let us say, for
dramatic literature but not
for history or philosophy), its disruptions could
be minimized. He would regard such counsel as extreme
naďveté. He would
allow, I imagine, that a
technology may be barred entry to a culture.
But we
may learn from Thamus the
following: once a technology is
admitted, it plays
out its hand; it does what
it is designed to do. Our task is to understand what
that design is—that is to
say, when we admit a new technology to the culture,
we must do so with our eyes
wide open.
From Chapter 1 of
Technopoly, “The Judgement of Thamus,”
by Neil Postman.