Teaching the Origins
Controversy:
Science, Or Religion, Or Speech?
David K. DeWolf*
Stephen C. Meyer**
Mark Edward DeForrest***
Table
of Contents Page
I. Introduction... 40
II. A Brief History of the Origins Controversy. 46
A. Classical
Science-Based Design Arguments.. 46
B. Darwin and
the Eclipse of Design. 48
C. Problems with
the Neo-Darwinian Synthesis and the
Re-emergence of Design........
49
III. May Spokes Teach Criticism? 56
IV. A Brief Introduction to Contemporary Design Theory 59
A. A Theory of
Intelligent Design. 59
B. Design
Theory: An Empirical Basis?. 61
V. But Is It Science? Darwinism, Design and Demarcation. 66
A. McLean v. Arkansas and the Definition of
Science 66
B. The Demise of
Demarcation Arguments.. 68
C. Majority
and Minority Opinions..... 73
D. Novel
Paradigms v. Establishment Science: Majority and
Minority Perspectives in Science.......
74
E. Daubert’s
Redefinition of Science 76
F. An Answer for
Spokes 78
VI. Is It Religion? The Theory of Intelligent Design and the
Establishment Clause 79
A. Defining
Religion 80
B. Applying
the Ninth Circuit’s Test for Religion 85
C. Do Religious
Implications Turn a Theory into Religion?. 87
D. Extending Edwards v. Aguillard to
Cover Design Theory? 90
E. The Legal
Differences Between Creation Science and
Design Theory. 93
F. A Residual Lemon Objection. 95
G. Back to
Spokes 98
VII. Is It Speech? Design Theory and Viewpoint Discrimination 100
A. The Rosenberger Revolution 103
B. Edwards v. Aguillard Revisited. 106
VIII.. Conclusion. 109
I. Introduction
One can hardly imagine a more contentious issue in the
American culture wars than the debate over how biological origins should be
taught in the public schools. On the one hand, the National Academy of
Sciences, the National Center for Science Education, and the American Civil
Liberties Union have insisted that any departure from a strictly Darwinian
approach to the issue constitutes an attack on science itself, and even an
unconstitutional intrusion of religion into the public school science
curriculum. On the other hand, many parents and religious activists have long
rebelled against what they perceive as a dogmatic attack on their religious
beliefs. Beginning in the 1970s, such activists sought to promote a Bible-based
curriculum—known as “scientific creationism”—as either a complement or an
alternative to the standard Darwinist curriculum advocated by the National
Academy of Sciences. And so the battle lines were drawn.
When confronted with a conflict between establishment
science and religious fundamentalism, most lawyers have assumed that the law
clearly favors the former. And indeed, although the creationists won some
battles in state legislatures during the 1980s, they clearly lost the war in
the courts. In McLean v. Arkansas Board of Educ.1
and Edwards v. Aguillard,2
the courts ruled that teaching “scientific creationism” or “creation-science”
would have resulted in an unconstitutional advancement of religion. Media
reports have portrayed all subsequent local controversies as reruns of these
earlier battles—some even invoking imagery from the Scopes trial from
the 1920s.3
Such reports have, unfortunately, served to obscure
rather than illuminate the legal issues that school boards and their lawyers
now increasingly face. Not only are the legal issues surrounding the Edwards
decision more complex than often reported, but the challenge to the Darwinian
curriculum in public education has now changed. Indeed, as the new century
begins, a school board lawyer is far less likely to confront a religion-based
challenge to the current biology curriculum than he is to face a situation
resembling the one portrayed in the following hypothetical:
John Spokes has been teaching biology for several
years at a public high school in Middletown, Anystate. In previous years,
Spokes has spent several class periods discussing Darwin’s theory of evolution,
providing students with a clear overview of the standard evidence and arguments
for contemporary Darwinian4
theory, as well as key concepts such as natural selection, random mutation, and
descent with modification that students need in order to understand the theory.
In addition to describing how biological evolution explains the origin of new
living forms from existing forms, he also has discussed how the theory of
chemical evolution explains the origin of the first life starting from simple
chemicals.
In his discussion of these theories, Spokes provided a
standard textbook treatment, never departing from the strictly naturalistic or
materialistic renderings of these theories that textbooks present. Thus, he
explained that the evolutionary process is “random and undirected” and that it
occurs “without either plan or purpose” as some textbooks phrase it.5 He has also explained that
Darwin’s theory explains the appearance of design in living organisms by the
“impersonal” mechanism of natural selection, and thus envisions no role for a
“guiding hand” or “intelligent designer” in the origin of new life forms.6 Following Ayala, and other
prominent biologists and biology textbook writers, Spokes has described
“Darwin’s greatest accomplishment” as precisely his ability to explain the
apparent design of living systems “without resort to a Creator or other
external agent.”7
Despite regular assurances to his students that
evolutionary theory does not conflict with religious belief, Spokes has
encountered increasing criticism of his teaching methods over several years.
True, some parents (and students) complain that his lessons conflict with the
Bible. Yet others have begun to complain that his lectures make “a selective
presentation of the scientific evidence.” This disturbs Spokes. After one
conversation with several parents, including a local physician and geneticist,
Spokes agrees to read several books and articles that they say will provide a
specifically scientific critique of contemporary Darwinian and chemical
evolutionary theory.
To his surprise, Spokes finds himself impressed with
much of what he reads. Articles from the American Biology Teacher, for
example, document rather egregious errors in textbooks presentations—errors
which have the effect of overstating the evidential case for neo-Darwinian and
chemical evolutionary theory.8 Spokes is disturbed to find that many of the
“icons” of evolution found in his textbook, such as Haeckel’s falsified
embryological drawings, the peppered moths, and the Miller-Urey experiment, are
seriously misleading.9
Other scientific articles suggest that textbooks
commit many errors of omission—errors that understate the evidential
difficulties with neo-Darwinian claims. In his reading, Spokes learns about the
so-called “Cambrian explosion,” a term describing the sudden appearance of most
of the major animal “phyla” (or “body plans”) in the Cambrian period (530 mya),
in clear contradiction to Darwinian expectations about the fossil record.
Spokes also notices that scientists writing in technical journals openly
discuss the challenge that these data pose to the neo-Darwinian prediction of
gradual step-by-step change.10
Yet Spokes knows that most basal biology texts do not even mention the Cambrian
explosion, let alone that it might challenge contemporary Darwinism.
Spokes’s reading on the Cambrian explosion sensitizes
him to another issue—one of definition. Spokes begins to suspect that textbooks
have created confusion by using the term “evolution” as though it were a
unitary concept, even though it can refer to everything from the universal
common ancestry thesis, to small-scale change, to large-scale innovation via
a strictly mindless material mechanism.11
Moreover, technical literature suggests that while Darwin’s mechanism of
natural selection acting on random variations explains small-scale
“micro-evolutionary” changes (such as the beak size and shape of the Galapagos
finches), it fails to explain the large scale “macro-evolutionary”
transformations required to build novel organs, body plans, and morphological
structures.12 It now seems
to Spokes that the equivocal use of terminology has led, again, to overstating
the scientific consensus about the sufficiency of neo-Darwinism. The failure to
define terms also seems to have created an “all or nothing approach” to the
subject of evolution that has prevented careful consideration of separate
propositions and a variety of possible views.
For example, by now Spokes has read about a number of
scientists who accept “evolution” in one or more of the senses described above,
but who do not accept the classical Darwinian explanation of apparent
design. Indeed, he notices that many scientists now question whether natural
selection (and other similarly naturalistic mechanisms) can explain away all
instances of “apparent design,” as classical Darwinism and modern neo-Darwinism
assert. Some of these scientists argue that certain features of living systems such
as “irreducibly complex” molecular machines in cells, or the “information
content of the DNA molecule,” suggest real design by a purposeful or
intelligent agent. Spokes finds these ideas provocative and fascinating, though
not altogether congenial to his own way of thinking. Nevertheless, he admits
that the scientists advancing these ideas have excellent credentials and appeal
to scientific evidence not religious authority. He finds a book by biochemist
Michael Behe, Darwin’s Black Box,13
particularly impressive in this regard.
After two summers of reading such materials, Spokes
finds himself in a quandary. Spokes is not entirely sure how to incorporate
what he has read into the way he teaches his high school students. For one
thing, he is not politically naive. He has read statements issued by the
National Academy of Sciences,14
the National Association of Biology Teachers,15
and the American Association for the Advancement of Science,16 which urge him to ignore any
criticism of Darwinism as unscientific and religiously motivated. He realizes
that he may be accused of “attacking science,” or “teaching creationism,” or
even “bringing religion into the science classroom.” Still, he finds it
troubling that his students learn nothing of important differences of opinion
among scientists, and he is confident that, regardless of anyone else’s
motivation, his motivation is only to “teach the controversy”17 and to discuss scientific evidence
and how scientists interpret it differently.
Spokes decides that at a minimum he must modify his
presentation to reflect the additional information and diversity of scientific
opinion that he has encountered in his study. In addition to presenting
evidence and arguments for the standard biological and chemical evolutionary
theory as he has done before, he plans four changes in his pedagogy. First, he
wants to correct the blatant factual errors in his textbook that overstate the
evidential case for neo-Darwinian and chemical evolutionary theory. Second, he
intends to tell students about the evidential challenges to these theories that
current textbooks fail to mention. Third, he wants to define the term
“evolution” without equivocation and to distinguish clearly between those
senses of the term that enjoy widespread support among scientists and those
that remain controversial, even if only among a minority of scientists.
Finally, he wants to tell his students that a growing minority of scientists do
see evidence of real, not just apparent, design in biological systems.
Wisely, Spokes decides to bring his plan to his
principal, and ultimately to the school board, to be sure he is on safe ground.
Is he?
Although this portrait of Spokes is hypothetical,18 the issues it raises are not.
Indeed, an increasing number of teachers around the country have begun to
implement very similar changes to their own biology curriculum, often, though
not always, creating controversy.19
School boards, fearing both ideological strife and costly litigation, have
often not known how to react to such teachers. On the one hand, forbidding any
dissent from Darwinian theory smacks of censorship. On the other, even school
board members sympathetic to such changes assume that federal law forbids
science educators to deviate from an exclusively Darwinian curriculum. In
short, many school boards do not know what the law allows.
This article will attempt to clarify what the law does
allow teachers to teach in their biology classrooms. In the process, it will
answer three key questions necessary to deciding the legal status of Spokes’s
proposed curriculum. These are:
•
Is It Science? Are Spokes’s intended changes in his biology
curriculum scientific? Is his plan to correct and critique textbook
presentations of neo-Darwinism scientific? Are the alternative theories that
Spokes wants to present (including the theory of intelligent design) scientific?
•
Is It Religion? Does Spokes’s plan to correct and critique textbook
presentations of neo-Darwinism constitute an establishment of religion? Does
Spokes’s plan to expose his students to evidence of design and design theory
qualify as teaching religion? Does the First Amendment prevent the presentation
of this point of view?
•
Is It Speech? Do Spokes’s plans to correct and critique textbook
presentations of neo-Darwinism, and to expose students to the alternative
theory of intelligent design, enjoy protection under the First Amendment,
either in the prohibition of viewpoint discrimination, or as an exercise of
academic freedom?
Before addressing these questions, however, we must
first place them in a broader historical context.
II. A Brief History of the Origins
Controversy
A. Classical
Science-Based Design Arguments
Prior to the publication of The Origin of Species
by Charles Darwin in 1859, many Western thinkers, for over two thousand years,
had answered the question “how did life arise?” by invoking the activity of a
purposeful designer or creator. Design arguments based upon observations of the
natural world were made by Greek and Roman philosophers such as Plato20 and Cicero,21 by Jewish philosophers such as
Maimonides, and by Christian thinkers such as Thomas Aquinas.22
The idea of design also figured centrally in the
modern scientific revolution (1500-1700).23
As historians of science have often pointed out, many of the founders of early
modern science assumed that the natural world was intelligible precisely
because they also assumed that it had been designed by a rational mind. In
addition, many individual scientists—Johannes Kepler in astronomy,24 John Ray (1627-1705) in biology,25 Robert Boyle (1627-1691) in
chemistry26—made specific
design arguments based upon empirical discoveries in their respective fields.
This tradition attained an almost majestic rhetorical quality in the writing of
Sir Isaac Newton, who made both elegant and sophisticated design arguments
based upon biological, physical, and astronomical discoveries. Writing in the
General Scholium to the Principia, Newton suggested that the stability
of the planetary system depended not only upon the regular action of universal
gravitation, but also upon the very precise initial positioning of the planets
and comets in relation to the sun. As he explained:
[T]hough these bodies may, indeed, continue in their
orbits by the mere laws of gravity, yet they could by no means have at first
derived the regular position of the orbits themselves from those
laws . . . [Thus] [t]his most beautiful system of the sun,
planets, and comets, could only proceed from the counsel and dominion of an
intelligent and powerful Being.27
Or as he wrote in the Opticks:
How came the Bodies of Animals to be contrived with so
much Art, and for what ends were their several parts? Was the Eye contrived
without Skill in Opticks, and the Ear without Knowledge of
Sounds? . . . And these things being rightly dispatch’d,
does it not appear from Phænomena that there is a Being incorporeal, living,
intelligent, omnipresent . . . .28
Despite the objections of some enlightenment
philosophers, notably David Hume, science-based design arguments continued well
into the early nineteenth century, especially in biology. William Paley’s
(1743-1805) Natural Theology, published in 1803 (several years after
Hume’s criticism of the design argument), is the most notable example. Paley’s
work catalogued a host of biological systems that suggested the work of a
superintending intelligence. He argued that the astonishing complexity and
superb adaptation of means to ends in such systems could not originate strictly
through the blind forces of nature, any more than could a complex machine such
as a pocket watch.29
B. Darwin
and the Eclipse of Design
Acceptance of the design argument finally began to
abate during the late nineteenth century with the emergence of increasingly
powerful materialistic explanations of apparent design, particularly Charles
Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection.30 Darwin argued in 1859 that living
organisms only appeared to be designed. To make this case, he proposed a
concrete mechanism, natural selection acting on random variations, that could
explain the adaptation of organisms to their environment (and other evidences
of apparent design) without actually invoking an intelligent or directing
agency. Darwin saw that natural forces would accomplish the work of a human
breeder, and thus that blind nature could come to mimic, over time, the action
of a selecting intelligence—a designer. If the origin of biological organisms
could be explained naturalistically,31
as Darwin argued, then explanations invoking an intelligent designer were
unnecessary and even vacuous.32
Even so, natural selection as a causal mechanism had a
mixed reception in the immediate post-Darwinian period. As the historian of
biology Peter Bowler has noted, classical Darwinism entered a period of
eclipse, in part because Darwin lacked a theory of the origin and transmission
of new heritable variation.33
By the late 1930s and 1940s, however, natural selection was revived as the main
engine of evolutionary change as developments in a number of fields helped to
clarify the nature of genetic variation.34
The resuscitation of the variation/natural selection mechanism by modern
genetics and population genetics became known as the neo-Darwinian synthesis.
According to the new synthetic theory of evolution, the mechanism of natural
selection acting upon random variations (especially including small-scale
mutations) sufficed to account for the origin of novel biological forms and
structures. Small-scale “microevolutionary” changes could be extrapolated
indefinitely to account for large-scale “macroevolutionary” development. With
the revival of natural selection, the neo-Darwinists would assert, like
Darwinists before them, that they had found a “designer substitute” that could
explain the appearance of design in biology as a result of the action of a
wholly natural mechanism.35
As Harvard evolutionary biologist Ernst Mayr has explained, “[T]he real core of
Darwinism . . . is the theory of natural selection. This theory is so important
for the Darwinian because it permits the explanation of adaptation, the
‘design’ of the natural theologian, by natural means.”36
C. Problems
with the Neo-Darwinian Synthesis
and the
Re-emergence of Design
Since the late 1960s, the modern synthesis that
emerged during the 1930s and 40s has begun to unravel in the face of new
developments in paleontology, systematics, molecular biology, genetics, and
developmental biology. Since then a series of technical articles and
books—including such recent titles as Evolution a Theory in Crisis
(1986) by Michael Denton, Darwinism: The Refutation of a Myth (1987) by
Soren Lovtrup, The Origins of Order (1993) by Stuart A. Kauffman, How
The Leopard Changed Its Spots (1994) by Brian C. Goodwin, Reinventing
Darwin (1995) by Niles Eldredge, The Shape of Life (1996) by
Rudolf A. Raff, Darwin’s Black Box (1996) by Michael Behe, The Origin
of Animal Body Plans (1997) by Wallace Arthur, Sudden Origins: Fossils,
Genes, and the Emergence of Species (1999) by Jeffrey H. Schwartz—have cast
doubt on the creative power of neo-Darwinism’s mutation/selection mechanism. As
a result, a search for alternative naturalistic mechanisms of innovation has
ensued with, as yet, no apparent success or consensus. So common are doubts
about the creative capacity of the selection/mutation mechanism,
neo-Darwinism’s “designer substitute,” that prominent spokesmen for
evolutionary theory must now periodically assure the public that “just because
we don’t know how evolution occurred, does not justify doubt about whether
it occurred.”37 As Niles
Eldredge wrote as early as 1982: “most observers see the current situation in
evolutionary theory—where the object is to explain how, not if, life evolves—as
bordering on total chaos.”38
Or as Stephen Gould wrote in 1980, “the neo-Darwinism synthesis is effectively
dead, despite its continued presence as textbook orthodoxy.”39
Indeed, scientists writing in technical journals
across the subdisciplines of biology have questioned neo-Darwinian theory on
many evidential and theoretical grounds, including:
(1) The neo-Darwinian mechanism of natural
selection acting on random variations does not seem sufficient to produce:
(a) novel specified genetic information,40
(b) “irreducibly complex,” “functionally
integrated” molecular machines and systems (such as bacterial motors, signal
transduction circuits or the blood clotting system),41
(c) novel organs and morphological structures
(such as wings, feathers, eyes, echo location, the amniotic egg, skin, nervous
systems, and multicellularity),42
or
(d) novel body plans.43
(2) Many significant mechanisms of evolutionary
change do not involve random mutations as the neo-Darwinian mechanism requires,
but instead seem to be directed by preprogrammed responses to environmental
stimuli.44
(3) The pattern of sudden appearance, missing
transitional forms,45 and “stasis”
in the fossil record—as seen in the “Cambrian explosion,” the “marine Mesozoic
revolution,” and the “big bloom” of angiosperm plant life, for example—does not
conform to neo-Darwinian expectations about the history of life.46
(4) Evidence from developmental biology suggests
clear limits to the amount of evolutionary change that organisms can undergo,
casting doubt on the Darwinian theory of common descent, and suggesting a
reason for morphological stasis in the fossil record.47
(5) Many homologous structures (and even some
proteins) derive from nonhomologous genes,48
while many dissimilar structures derive from similar genes, in both cases
contradicting neo-Darwinian expectations.49
(6) The (inferred) developmental programs among
the metazoan animals of the Cambrian period are strikingly dissimilar (or “not
conserved”), contrary to neo-Darwinian expectations.50
(7) The genetic code has not proven to be
“universal,” contrary to neo-Darwinian expectations based upon the theory of
universal common descent.51
Further, biochemists and origin-of-life researchers
have challenged the standard Oparin/Miller chemical evolutionary theory for the
origin of the first life for many reasons including:
(1) geochemists have failed to find
evidence of the nitrogen-rich “prebiotic soup” required by the standard
chemical evolutionary model.52
(2) The remains of single-celled organisms
in the very oldest rocks testify that life emerged more quickly than the
standard model (or any other) envisions or can explain.53
(3) Geological and geochemical evidence
suggests that prebiotic atmospheric conditions were hostile, not friendly, to
the production of amino acids and other essential building blocks of life.54
(4) In virtue of (3), experiments (such as
Stanley Miller’s) allegedly simulating the origin of pre-biotic building blocks
have no relevance to actual early earth processes.55
(5) Origin-of-life researchers lack
plausible explanations for the origin of the specified information in DNA
necessary to build essential proteins.56
(6) Origin of life researchers lack any
plausible explanations for the origin of the functionally integrated
information processing system present in even the simplest cells.57
Basal biology textbooks have almost universally failed
to report these and other difficulties found in recent technical literature.58 Instead, standard textbooks
continue to affirm both neo-Darwinian and chemical evolutionary theory
unequivocally and without qualification. Moreover, as noted in our
hypothetical, many texts continue to include significant factual errors, either
of omission or commission—though Spokes is hypothetical, the problems in the
texts are not.59
III. May Spokes Teach Criticism?
It may seem obvious that there can be no rationally
defensible grounds for preventing teachers from exposing students to
well-documented scientific critique of a theory or obsolete textbook material.
Nevertheless, teachers like Spokes often feel an understandable reluctance to
break with textbook orthodoxy and expose students to articles and other
supplementary materials documenting problems with neo-Darwinism or its textbook
presentation. Indeed, many official spokespersons for an exclusively Darwinist
curriculum now treat any criticism of neo-Darwinian (or chemical evolutionary)
theory as tantamount to an attack on science itself. Others assume that
criticism necessarily derives from religious motive or equate critique with
advocacy of “creationism.”
This rhetorical strategy fails for several reasons.
First, it implicitly equates a particular theory of biological origins—albeit a
long dominant one—with the science of biology itself. In no other field would
such a self-serving rhetoric stand unchallenged for long. Imagine the Freudians
equating psychology with the Freudian theory of the mind or the advocates of
phlogiston equating their theory with the field of chemistry itself. Science
has long involved theoretical competition among multiple competing hypotheses
and explanations. Science, therefore, requires criticism as well as the
articulation and defense of reigning theories. Thus, those biologists who seek
to insulate their preferred theories from critique by rhetorical
gerrymandering—that is, by equating dominant evolutionary theories with science
itself and then treating all criticism of such theories as necessarily
“unscientific”—themselves act in a profoundly unscientific manner.
Note, secondly, the list of evidential difficulties
cited above. Each can be found in standard scientific journals—journals such as
Paleobiology or Developmental Biology or Natural History.
Of course, some religiously-motivated creationists may want to make polemical
use of these evidential difficulties. Yet, that does not mean that scientific
critique of neo-Darwinism necessarily conceals a religious motive, if indeed
motive is even germane to deciding the scientific legitimacy of this critique.
In any case, the pedagogical issue is not the motive of the critics, but the
existence of specifically empirical critique of neo-Darwinian and chemical
evolutionary theory that textbooks do not report to students. Spokes wants to
eliminate this disparity between textbook presentations and the current state
of the scientific discussion of the issue. This hardly seems to constitute
either “religious” or “unscientific” activity.
To illustrate this point more concretely, consider an
example mentioned above. Origin-of-life researchers now acknowledge that
Stanley Miller’s famous experiment simulating the production of amino acids
under allegedly pre-biotic early earth conditions does not support chemical evolutionary
theory. Origin-of-life scientists, including Miller himself,60 now admit that no evidence
supports the strongly “reducing” mixture of gases that Miller assumed in his
1953 experiment. Indeed, considerable geochemical evidence now contradicts that
assumption.61 They also
know that if simulation experiments are rerun with more realistic mixtures of
gases they do not produce amino acids in any appreciable yields. Yet most basal
biology textbooks do not report any of these scientific developments.62
If Spokes reports these developments, can anyone
credibly maintain that he has acted in an “unscientific” or “religious” manner?
Instead, Spokes critics act in a most illiberal way. By stigmatizing critique
as either “unscientific” or “religious,” advocates for the exclusive
presentation of orthodox evolutionary theories discourage teachers from
teaching students what scientists actually know and report in their technical
journals, and encourage instead the presentation of a simplistic caricature of
scientific method and the origins controversy.
Of course, some Darwinist advocacy groups have
expressed concern that providing critique of, as well as evidence and arguments
for, orthodox evolutionary theories would confuse students.63 But clearly students would not be
well served by presenting a false picture of agreement where in fact there is
controversy. Indeed, even a prominent Darwinist, Will Provine, has complained
that this failure to present the controversy makes science education deadly
dull and robs it of the interest that would motivate students.64 Granted, textbook presentations in
many fields fail to capture the full richness and detail of front-line
research. But the errors of fact in many basal biology texts do not seem to
reflect mere oversimplifications. Instead, many are egregious, easy to correct,
and almost universally overstate the evidential support for orthodox
evolutionary theories. Thus, there is every reason to encourage Spokes to speak
to students about the existence of evidential criticism of neo-Darwinism in the
scientific literature and to correct textbooks where they are clearly in error.
Of course, the question of the legitimacy of Spokes’s
intended curricular change involves another issue. Recall that Spokes does not
intend merely to expose students to scientific critique of neo-Darwinism. He
also now intends to teach them about an alternative theory—known as “the theory
of intelligent design” or “design theory”—that directly challenges a key
proposition of both neo-Darwinian and chemical evolutionary theory, namely, the
denial of actual design in biology. Of course, if the neo-Darwinian mechanism
cannot explain the origin of apparent design, as many biologists have argued,
then some scientists will quite reasonably want to reconsider the possibility
of actual (i.e., intelligent) design as an alternative explanation. Not
surprisingly, many scientists have done exactly that and teachers like Spokes
will increasingly want to tell their students about this development in
science. Nevertheless, Spokes’s desire to teach about design raises additional
issues. Some have argued that “design theory” does not qualify as a scientific
theory. Others have maintained that it constitutes an establishment of
religion, or at least a religious theory. To assess the legality of Spokes’s
entire curriculum, therefore, requires making an assessment of the scientific
and religious status of “design theory.” Before we can do this we must review
the main tenets and features of this theory.
IV. A Brief Introduction to
Contemporary Design Theory
Since the 1980s, a growing number of scientists have
asserted that, contrary to neo-Darwinian orthodoxy, nature displays abundant
evidence of real, not just apparent, design. These scientists, known as design
theorists, advocate an alternative theory of biological origins known as
design theory or the theory of intelligent design (sometimes
abbreviated simply design). They have developed design theory in such
books as Darwin’s Black Box,65
The Mystery of Life’s Origin,66
Of Pandas and People,67
Mere Creation68 and The
Design Inference,69
as well as in articles in scientific and technical journals. Design theory
holds that intelligent causes rather than undirected natural causes best explain
many features of living systems. During recent years design theorists have
developed both a general theory of design detection and many specific empirical
arguments to support their views.
A. A
Theory of Intelligent Design
Developments in the information sciences have recently
made possible the articulation of criteria by which intelligently designed
systems can be identified by the kinds of patterns they exhibit. In a recent
book titled The Design Inference,70
published by Cambridge University Press, mathematician and probability theorist
William Dembski notes that rational agents often infer or detect the prior
activity of other designing minds by the character of the effects they leave
behind.71 Archaeologists
assume, for example, that rational agents produced the inscriptions on the
Rosetta Stone. Insurance fraud investigators detect certain “cheating patterns”
that suggest intentional manipulation of circumstances rather than “natural”
disasters. Cryptographers distinguish between random signals and those that
carry encoded messages. Dembski’s work shows that recognizing the activity of
intelligent agents constitutes a common and fully rational mode of inference.72
More importantly, Dembski’s work explicates the
criteria by which rational agents recognize the effects of other rational
agents, and distinguish them from the effects of natural causes. He argues that
systems or sequences that have the joint properties of “high complexity” (or
low probability) and “specification”73
invariably result from intelligent causes, not chance or physical-chemical
laws.74 As it turns out,
these criteria are equivalent (or “isomorphic”) to the notion of specified
information or information content. Thus, Dembski’s work suggests that “high
information content” indicates prior intelligent activity. This theoretical
insight comports with common, as well as scientific, experience. Few rational people
would, for example, attribute hieroglyphic inscriptions to natural forces such
as wind or erosion; instead, they would immediately recognize the activity of
intelligent agents. Dembski’s work shows why: Our reasoning involves a
comparative evaluation process that he represents with a device he calls “the
explanatory filter.”75 The filter
outlines a formal method by which scientists (as well as ordinary people)
decide among three different types of explanations: chance, necessity, and
design.76 His “explanatory
filter” constitutes, in effect, a scientific method for detecting the effects
of intelligence.77
B. Design
Theory: An Empirical Basis?
In addition to making use of a formal theory
articulating the criteria by which intelligent causes can be detected in the
“echo of their effects,” design theorists point to specific empirical evidence
of design, both in biology and physics. They argue that biological organisms in
particular display distinctive features of intelligently designed systems.
Indeed, a growing number of scientists are now willing to consider
alternatives to strictly naturalistic origins theories. Many now see especially
striking evidence of design in biology, even if much of it is still reported by
scientists and journals that presuppose a neo-Darwinian perspective.
In 1998, for example, the leading journal Cell
featured a special issue on “Macromolecular Machines.”78 All cells use complex molecular
machines to process information, build proteins, and move materials back and
forth across their membranes. Bruce Alberts, President of the National Academy
of Sciences, introduced this issue with an article entitled, The Cell as a
Collection of Protein Machines.79
In it, he stated that
We have always underestimated
cells. . . .
. . . .
The entire cell can be viewed as a factory that
contains an elaborate network of interlocking assembly lines, each of which is
composed of a set of large protein machines. . . .
. . . .
Why do we call the large protein assemblies that
underlie cell function protein machines? Precisely because, like
machines invented by humans to deal efficiently with the macroscopic world,
these protein assemblies contain highly coordinated moving parts
. . . .80
Alberts notes that molecular machines strongly
resemble machines designed by human engineers.81
Although, as an orthodox neo-Darwinist, he denies any role for actual, as
opposed to apparent, design in the origin of these systems.82
In recent years, however, some scientists have
formulated a formidable challenge to the neo-Darwinian view. For example, in Darwin’s
Black Box, Lehigh University biochemist Michael Behe shows that
neo-Darwinists have failed to explain the origin of complex molecular machines
in living systems.83 Behe
examines the acid-powered rotary engines that turn the whiplike flagella of
certain bacteria.84 He shows
that the intricate machinery in this molecular motor—including a rotor, a
stator, O-rings, bushings, and a drive shaft—requires the coordinated
interaction of approximately forty complex protein parts.85 The absence of any one of these
proteins would result in the complete loss of motor function. To suggest that
such an “irreducibly complex” engine emerged gradually in a Darwinian fashion
strains credulity. Natural selection selects functionally advantageous systems.
Yet motor function only ensues after all necessary parts have
independently self-assembled—an astronomically improbable event.
Thus, Behe insists that Darwinian mechanisms cannot
account for the origin of molecular motors and other such “irreducibly complex”
systems that require the coordinated interaction of multiple, independent
protein parts.86 To emphasize
his point, Behe has conducted a literature search of relevant technical
journals.87 He found a complete
absence of gradualistic Darwinian explanations for the origin of the systems
and motors that he discusses.88
Behe concludes that neo-Darwinists have not explained nor, in most cases, even
attempted to explain, how the appearance of design in “irreducibly complex”
systems arose naturally.89
Instead, he notes that we know of only one cause
sufficient to produce functionally integrated, irreducibly complex
systems—intelligent design.90
Whenever we encounter irreducibly complex systems and we know how they arose,
invariably a designer played a causal role. Thus, Behe concludes on the basis
of our knowledge of present cause and effect relationships (in accord with the
standard uniformitarian method employed in the historical sciences) that the
molecular machines and complex systems we observe in cells probably resulted
from an intelligent cause.91
In brief, molecular motors appear designed because they were designed.
The publication of Behe’s book in 1996 generated
international acclaim and critique in over eighty book reviews. Even his
critics have generally conceded the scientific accuracy of Behe’s claims
(including his literature search showing the complete absence of neo-Darwinian
explanations for many of the irreducibly complex systems that he examines).
They have mainly objected to his argument on philosophical and methodological
grounds. Behe’s critics claim that to infer an intelligent cause for the origin
of these complex systems (as Behe does) “goes beyond science.” (We discuss this
objection in Section V below).
Despite such criticism, Behe is not alone in his
conclusions. Consider the case of Professor Dean Kenyon. For nearly twenty
years, Professor Kenyon was a leading evolutionary theorist who specialized in
origin-of-life biology. While at San Francisco State College in 1969 he
coauthored Biochemical Predestination,92
a book that defined evolutionary thinking on the origin-of-life for over a
decade. Kenyon’s theory attempted to show how complex biomolecules such as
proteins and DNA might have “self-organized” via strictly chemical forces.93 Yet as Kenyon reflected more on
the recent developments in molecular biology about the complexity of living
things, he began to question whether undirected chemistry could really produce
the information-rich molecules found even in “simple” cells. Studies of the
genetic molecule DNA revealed that it functions in much the same way as a
machine code or a text in a book. As Richard Dawkins notes, “The machine code
of the genes is uncannily computer like.”94
Or, as software innovator Bill Gates notes, “DNA is like a computer program,
but far, far more advanced than any software we’ve ever created.”95 Studies in molecular biology and
information theory have shown that the assembly instructions inscribed along
the spine of DNA display the characteristic hallmarks of intelligently encoded
information: both the complexity and specificity of function that, according to
Dembski’s theory, indicate design.96
As a result of this evidence, Kenyon and many other scientists (notably Charles
Thaxton, Walter Bradley, and Roger Olsen), as well as philosophers of science,
have concluded that the “specified complexity” or high information content of
DNA—like the information in a computer program, an ancient scroll, or in this
article—had an intelligent source.97
In recent years the fossil record has also provided
new support for design. Fossil studies reveal a “biological big bang” near the
beginning of the Cambrian period 530 million years ago.98 At that time
roughly forty separate major groups of organisms or “phyla” (including most all
the basic body plans of modern animals) emerged suddenly without evident
precursors.99 Although
neo-Darwinian theory requires vast periods of time for the step-by-step
development of new biological organs and body plans, fossil finds have
repeatedly confirmed a pattern of explosive appearance and prolonged stability
in living forms.100 Moreover,
the fossil record also shows a “top-down” hierarchical pattern of appearance in
which major structural themes or body plans emerge before minor variations on
those themes.101 Not only
does this pattern directly contradict the “bottom-up” pattern predicted by
neo-Darwinism, but as University of San Francisco marine paleobiologist Paul
Chien and several colleagues have argued, it also strongly resembles the
pattern evident in the history of human technological design.102 This pattern
suggests actual (i.e., intelligent) design as the best explanation for
empirical data.103
Other scientists now see evidence of design in the
information processing system of the cell, the signal transduction circuitry of
the cell, the complexity and specificity of proteins, the end-directed
embryological processes of organismal development, the complexity of the human brain,
and even the phenomenon known as “homology” (evidence previously thought to
provide unequivocal support for neo-Darwinianism).104 Design theorists
have begun to marshal an impressive array of empirical evidence in support of
their perspective, thus challenging standard evolutionary theories for the
origin and development of life across a variety of subdisciplines within the
biology sciences.105
However, the legal and educational point at issue is
not whether design theorists are right in their scientific claims, but whether
their work may be discussed in science classrooms of public high schools.
Setting aside for the moment concerns about the constitutional issues raised by
the possible religious implications of design theory, teachers and school
boards must assess whether information about the work of scientists (such as
Behe, Kenyon, Thaxton, Chien, Dembski and others) has a legitimate place in a
public school biology classroom.
The discussion above demonstrates that, right or
wrong, the work of such scientists is clearly germane to the topic of
biological origins. As noted, Darwin’s theory (and other similarly naturalistic
origins theories) sought explicitly to explain the appearance of design in
biology without reference to an actual designer.106 Thus, it is
misleading to suggest, as many do, that Darwinism and design theory address two
different subjects: one scientific, and the other religious. Rather, both
Darwinism and design represent competing answers to the very same question: how
did living forms (with their appearance of design) arise and diversify on
earth? At present, many biology texts explain the evidence and arguments for
the efficacy of natural selection and random variation—neo-Darwinism’s
“designer substitute.”107
Good science education requires that students learn and understand such
evidence and arguments. Yet, if many well-credentialed scientists now dispute
the adequacy of the neo-Darwinian mechanism (and other similarly materialistic
theories), and some now publicly advocate the (actual) design hypothesis, then
surely their work is relevant to a discussion of the scientific issues raised
by neo-Darwinian theory. At the very least, knowing the evidence and arguments for
design will help students understand the full intellectual significance of
neo-Darwinism in its current context.108
More importantly, exposure to these ideas will help correct the current
imbalance in the presentation of this issue in current basal biological texts.
V. But Is It Science? Darwinism, Design, and Demarcation
Of course, critics of design theory generally do not
dispute the data (as opposed to the interpretation) that design theorists
marshal in support of their view, nor do they disagree that some evidence might
be interpreted to support the idea of design. They argue instead that the very
notion of “intelligent design” is inherently unscientific—that design theory
does not qualify as science according to established definitions of the term.
To justify this claim critics cite various definitional or demarcation criteria
that purport to define science and distinguish it (or provide “demarcation,”
from pseudoscience, metaphysics, or religion).109
These kinds of arguments have previously played an important role in deciding
the scientific, and consequently legal, status of “creation science.” Moreover, they continue to cast doubt on the
scientific status of other alternatives to strictly naturalistic origins
theories, including design theory.
A. McLean
v. Arkansas and the Definition of Science
In 1982, a federal judge adopted a five-point
definition of science as part of his finding that a law requiring Arkansas
public schools to teach “creation science” alongside standard neo-Darwinian
theory was unconstitutional.110
While there are decisive differences between design theory and creation
science,111 critics of design
theory often rely upon the McLean criteria112 to establish
definitional or methodological norms.
In McLean, Judge William Overton ruled that an
Arkansas law requiring the teaching of “creation science” in public schools
violated the First Amendment’s establishment clause.113 He based his
decision not only on the Establishment Clause, but upon a finding that
so-called “creation science” does not qualify as science.114 Indeed, he
reasoned that because creation science does not qualify as science it
constituted religion.115
In making his determination, Judge Overton relied upon the expert testimony of
the Darwinian philosopher of science Michael Ruse.116 In his expert
testimony, Ruse and other expert witnesses asserted a five-point definition of
science that provided allegedly normative criteria for determining whether a
theory qualifies as scientific.117
Any theory, according to Ruse, which failed to meet these five criteria could
not be considered to be “scientific.”118
According to Ruse, for a theory to be scientific it must be:
(1) guided by natural law;
(2) explanatory by natural law;
(3) testable against the empirical world;
(4) tentative in its conclusions; and
(5) falsifiable.119
Ruse further testified that creation science—in part
because it invoked the singular action of a creator as the cause of certain
events in the history of life—could never meet these criteria.120 Thus, he
concluded that creationism might be true, but it could never qualify as
science.121 Judge Overton
ultimately agreed, adopting Ruse’s five demarcation criteria as part of his
opinion.122
Although the case was in some ways superseded by the
subsequent ruling of the United States Supreme Court in Edwards v. Aguillard,123 the McLean
case, and the philosophy of science that underwrites it, poses an implied
challenge to the scientific status of all theories of origin (including design
theory) that invoke singular, intelligent causes as opposed to strictly
material causes.124 If design
theory does not qualify as science, as Ruse testified and the court ruled
concerning creation science, then, at least as a pedagogical matter, design
theory does not belong in the science classroom.
B. The
Demise of Demarcation Arguments
Notwithstanding the favorable reception that Michael
Ruse enjoyed in Judge Overton’s courtroom, many prominent philosophers of
science, including Larry Laudan and Philip Quinn125 (neither of whom
supported creation science’s empirical claims), soon repudiated Ruse’s
testimony on the grounds that, as Laudan argued, it “canoniz[ed] a false
stereotype of what science is and how it works.”126 These
philosophers of science insisted that Ruse’s testimony seriously misrepresented
contemporary thinking in the philosophy of science about the status of the
demarcation problem.127
Indeed, it now seems clear for several reasons that the philosophy of science
provides no grounds for disqualifying nonmaterialistic alternatives to
Darwinism as inherently “unscientific.”
First, as Laudan noted, many philosophers of science
have generally abandoned attempts to define science by reference to abstract
demarcation criteria.128
Indeed, they have found it notoriously difficult to define science generally
via the kind of methodological criteria that Ruse and the court promulgated in
the McLean case—in part because proposed demarcation criteria have
inevitably fallen prey to death by counterexample.129 Well established
scientific theories often lack some of the presumably necessary features of
true science (e.g., falsifiability, observability, repeatability, use of
lawlike explanation, etc.), while many poorly supported, disreputable, or
“crank” ideas often meet some of these same criteria.
Consider, for example, the criteria of falsifiability
and tentativeness, two key and related litmus tests in the 1981 McLean
trial.130 Although Ruse
asserts that all truly scientific theories are held tentatively by their
proponents and are readily falsifiable by contradictory evidence, the history
of science tells a very different story. As Imre Lakatos, one of the premier
historians and philosophers of science of the twentieth century, showed in the
1970s, some of the most powerful scientific theories have been constructed by
those who stubbornly refused to reject their theories in the face of anomalous
data.131 For example, on
the basis of his theory of universal gravitation, Sir Isaac Newton made a
number of predictions about the position of planets that did not materialize.132 Nevertheless,
rather than rejecting the notion of universal gravitation he refined his
“auxiliary assumptions” (e.g., the assumption that planets are perfectly
spherical and influenced only by gravitational force) and left his core theory
in place.133 As
Lakatos showed, the explanatory flexibility of Newton’s theory in the face of
apparently falsifying evidence turned out to be one of its greatest strengths.134 Such flexibility
emphatically did not compromise universal gravitation’s “scientific status” as
Ruse’s definition of science would imply.135
On the other hand, the history of science is littered
with the remains of failed theories that have been falsified, not by the
air-tight disproof of a single anomaly, but by the judgment of the scientific
community concerning the preponderance of data.136 Are such
falsified, and therefore falsifiable, theories (e.g., the flat earth,
phlogiston, geocentricism, flood geology, etc.) more scientific than successful
theories (such as Newton’s was in, say, 1750) that possess wide-ranging explanatory
power?
As a result of such contradictions, most contemporary
philosophers of science have come to regard the question, “what distinguishes
science from non-science,” as both intractable and uninteresting. Instead,
philosophers of science have increasingly realized that the real issue is not
whether a theory is “scientific” according to some abstract definition, but
whether a theory is true, or warranted by the evidence. As Laudan explains, “If
we would stand up and be counted on the side of reason, we ought to drop terms
like
‘pseudo-science’ . . . they . . . do
only emotive work for us.”137 As Martin Eger has summarized,
“[d]emarcation arguments have collapsed. Philosophers of science don’t hold
them anymore. They may still enjoy acceptance in the popular world, but that’s
a different world.”138
Second, even if one assumes for the sake of argument
that criteria could be found to demarcate science in general from nonscience in
general, the specific demarcation criteria used in the McLean case have
proven utterly incapable of discriminating the scientific status of
materialistic and non-materialistic origins theories.139 Laudan noted, for
example, that Judge Overton’s opinion made much of creation science’s inability
to be tested or falsified.140
Yet, as Laudan argues, the claim that
Creationism is neither falsifiable nor testable is to
assert that Creationism makes no empirical assertions whatever. That is surely
false. Creationists make a wide range of testable assertions about matters of
fact. Thus, as Judge Overton himself grants (apparently without seeing its
implications), the creationists say that the earth is of very recent
origin . . . they argue that most of the geological features
of the earth’s surface are diluvial in character . . . they
assert the limited variability of species. They are committed to the view that,
since animals and man were created at the same time, the human fossil record
must be paleontologically co-extensive with the record of lower animals.141
Laudan notes that, though creation scientists “are
committed to a large number of factual . . . claims,”
available evidence contradicts their empirical claims.142 As he explains, “no
one has shown how to reconcile such claims with the available evidence—evidence
which speaks persuasively to a long earth history, among other things. In
brief, these claims are testable, they have been tested, and they have failed
those tests.”143
Yet, Laudan notes, if creationist arguments have been
shown false by empirical evidence (as Ruse and other expert witnesses at the
Arkansas trial no doubt believed), then creation science must be falsifiable.144 But if it is
falsifiable, then by Ruse’s own criterion, it must qualify as scientific.
Similar problems have afflicted Ruse’s other
demarcation criteria. For example, insofar as both creationist and evolutionary
theories make historical claims about past causal events, both theories offer
causal explanations that are not explained by natural law. The theory of common
descent, a central thesis of the Origin of Species, does not explain by
natural law. Common descent explains by postulating hypothetical historical
events (and a pattern of events) which, if actual, would explain a variety of
presently observed data.145
The theory of common descent makes claims about what happened in the
past—namely that unobserved transitional organisms existed—forming a
genealogical bridge between presently existing life forms.146 Thus, on the
theory of common descent, a postulated pattern of events, not a law, does the
main explanatory work. Similarly, as Laudan notes, scientists often make
“existence claims” about past events or present processes without knowing the
natural laws on which they depend.147
As he notes, “Darwin took himself to have established the existence of [the
mechanism of] natural selection almost a half century before geneticists were
able to lay out the laws of heredity on which natural selection depended.”148 Thus, Ruse’s
second demarcation criterion would require, if applied consistently,
classifying both creation science and classical Darwinism (as well as
much of neo-Darwinism) as unscientific. As Laudan notes,
If we took the McLean Opinion criterion
seriously, we should have to say that . . . Darwin [was] unscientific; and, to
take an example from our own time, it would follow that plate tectonics is
unscientific because we have not yet identified the laws of physics and
chemistry which account for the dynamics of crustal motion.149
Third, analyses of the demarcation problem have
suggested that naturalistic and non-naturalistic origins theories (including
both Darwinism and design theory) are “methodologically equivalent,” both in
their ability to meet various demarcation criteria and as historical theories
of origin. As noted above, Laudan’s critique suggests that when the specific
demarcation criteria promulgated in the McLean case are applied rigidly
they disqualify both Darwinism and various nonmaterialistic alternatives.150 Yet as his
discussion of falsification suggests, if certain criteria are applied more
liberally then both theories may qualify as scientific. More recent studies in
the philosophy of science have confirmed and amplified Laudan’s analysis.151 They suggest that
philosophically neutral criteria do not exist that can define science narrowly
enough to disqualify theories of creation or design without also disqualifying
Darwinism and/or other materialistic evolutionary theories on identical
grounds.152 Either science
will be defined so narrowly as to disqualify both types of theory, or science
must be defined more broadly, and the initial reasons for excluding opposing
theories will evaporate. Thus, materialistic and nonmaterialistic origins
theories appear to be methodologically equivalent with respect to a wide range
of demarcation criteria—that is, both appear equally scientific or equally
unscientific provided the same methdological criteria are used to adjudicate
their scientific status (and provided philosophically neutral criteria are
used to make such assessments).
Indeed, recent work on the historical sciences
suggests deep methodological and logical similarities between various origins
theories. Philosopher of biology, Elliot Sober, has argued that both classical
design arguments and the Darwinian argument for descent with modification
constitute attempts to make inferences to the best explanation.153 Other work in the
philosophy of science has shown that both Darwinism and design theory attempt
to answer characteristically historical questions: both may have metaphysical
implications or overtones; both employ characteristically historical forms of
inference, explanation, and testing; and both are subject to similar
epistemological limitations.154
C. Majority
and Minority Opinions
Accordingly, even many of those who previously wielded
demarcation arguments as a way of protecting the Darwinist hegemony in public
education, including the most prominent advocates of these arguments, have
either abandoned or repudiated them.155
For example, Eugenie Scott of The National Center for Science Education (an
advocacy group for an exclusively Darwinist curriculum) no longer seeks to
dismiss creation science as pseudoscience or as unscientific; instead, she
argues that it constitutes “bad science.”156
Scott no longer repudiates design theory as inherently “unscientific,” as she
did as recently as 1994; she now argues it is a minority viewpoint within
science.157 Similarly, during
a talk to the American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) in
1993, Michael Ruse himself repudiated his previous support for the demarcation
principle by admitting that Darwinism (like creationism) “depends upon certain
unprovable metaphysical assumptions.”158
In his more recent scholarship, Ruse has openly argued that evolutionary theory
has often functioned as a kind of “secular religion.”159
D. Novel
Paradigms vs. Establishment Science:
Majority and
Minority Perspectives in Science
The demise of demarcation arguments within the
philosophy of science has made it difficult for critics of design (or other
non-naturalistic origins theories) to label them unscientific in principle. As
Laudan and others have argued, the status and merit of competing origins theories
must be decided on the basis of empirical evidence and argument, not upon
abstract philosophical or methodological litmus tests.160 Yet as we have
seen, design theorists in particular make extensive appeals to such empirical
evidence and argument. Moreover, if, arguably, design theory has both a
theoretical basis and evidential support, and if it meets abstract definitional
criteria of scientific status equally as well as its main theoretical rivals,
then it seems natural to ask: on what grounds can design theory now be excluded
from public school science curriculum?
Some have claimed that design theory is too new to
merit discussion in biology classrooms, and no doubt this does partially explain
its frequent omission.161
Nevertheless, the relative novelty of design theory does not justify its
exclusion on either legal or pedagogical grounds. Indeed, quite the reverse is
the case. The law provides no guidelines for determining how long a scientific
theory must have existed in order to warrant teaching students about it.
Further, good teachers know that exposing students to new (and even
controversial) ideas can stimulate student interest and engagement and lead to
greater subject mastery. Nor does science itself have a governing body that can
issue binding rulings about such matters. Instead, this constitutes a matter
for local teachers and school boards to decide.
Other critics of design have asserted another reason
for exclusion: its minority status within science.162 Until design
theory wins the support of the majority of scientists, they argue, students may
not be exposed to the evidence or arguments for it.163 Yet such a view
seems profoundly at odds with scientific practice, which itself involves
dialogue and debate between scientists, some of whom advocate, from time to
time, for new interpretations against established views. Those who insist that
teachers may present only the majority view on a scientific issue, or that only
majority opinions constitute “the scientific perspective,” overlook the history
of science. Many established scientific theories originally met opposition from
the majority of scientists. And science often involves argument between
competing theoretical perspectives. As the Supreme Court stated in Daubert
v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc.,164
“Scientific conclusions are subject to perpetual revision. . . .
The scientific project is advanced by broad and wide-ranging consideration of a
multitude of hypotheses, for those that are incorrect will eventually be shown
to be so, and that in itself is an advance.”165
Since, again, no ruling body in science can determine when a minority
scientific interpretation has attracted sufficient support to warrant
discussion in the science classroom, the pedagogical debate will necessarily,
and properly, devolve to individual teachers and local school boards. In any
case, defining permissible science as co-extensive with majority scientific
opinion erects a more restrictive standard than the law itself now recognizes
in deciding the admissibility of expert scientific opinion.
E. Daubert’s
Redefinition of Science
For seventy years the exclusion of minority scientific
views as evidence was enshrined in Frye v. United States.166 At his trial for
murder, James Alphonzo Frye offered systolic blood pressure taken during
pre-trial questioning—essentially an early, crude type of polygraph—to prove
his innocence.167 In
affirming the trial court’s refusal to admit the testimony, the D.C. Circuit
noted that this form of evidence had not been generally accepted within the
appropriate scientific disciplines.168
It then ruled that the test of reliability—and thus of admissibility—was
general acceptance within the scientific community.169 Although Frye
was widely followed,170
it was also criticized.171
In 1989, Frye’s hold on the courts was broken
when the Maine Supreme Court abandoned Maine’s version of the Frye rule.172 The acceptance of
certain “clinical features” by an expert’s profession “does not establish the
scientific reliability of [the expert’s] conclusions.”173 Whether or not an
opinion can qualify as scientific is determined by the quantity and quality of
empirical support upon which the assertion
is based.174
Four years later, the United States Supreme Court
decided Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc.175 Daubert
arose from a claim that Merrell Dow’s drug, Bendectin, had caused birth
defects.176 Noting that the
Federal Rules of Evidence are to be liberally construed in favor of
admissibility,177 the Court
found that Frye’s “general acceptance” test was too restrictive;
instead, trial courts should admit evidence if it is “supported by appropriate
validation—i.e., ‘good grounds,’ based on what is known.”178 Since the
hallmark for science under Daubert is “evidentiary reliability,”179 Daubert
heralds a critical shift in the judicial system’s understanding of the nature
of science itself.180 As more
states abandon Frye in favor of the rule announced in Daubert,181 scientific claims
will be evaluated not on the basis of a popularity poll among scientists or by
the fulfillment of a set of arbitrary criteria.182 Instead, the test
for scientific legitimacy comes from the validation of the empirical research
supporting the evidence.183
This trend makes reliance upon the demarcation
criteria in McLean v. Arkansas even more questionable. Since Daubert
has made the question of scientific legitimacy turn on “evidentiary
reliability,”184 the
courtroom should be hospitable to competing theories provided each theory has
an empirical basis. To exclude an interpretation simply because it has not yet
achieved majority support usurps the function that juries ought to serve.185 By analogy, the
debate over origins theory should not exclude a viewpoint at the outset because
of the inability to command a majority of scientists; it should be the function
of scientific inquiry itself to permit competing theories to argue, on the
basis of empirical data, for wider acceptance.186
F. An
Answer for Spokes
It is hard to conceive of a legitimate objection to
Spokes’s plan to correct errors in basal biology textbooks, including both
errors of omission and commission. To the contrary, refusing to permit
criticism contradicts the scientific commitment to open argument and
self-correction. If refusing to permit criticism would be illiberal, then
refusing to permit the discussion of alternative theories would be illogical.
As noted, neo-Darwinism claims to have found a mechanism that can explain the
appearance of design in biology without recourse to an actual designer.187 If this mechanism
cannot explain the appearance of design, as many scientists now argue, then it
is likely that some scientists at least will want to consider actual design as
a better explanation. Scientific critique of the mechanism that functions as a
designer substitute leads logically to reconsideration of the need for a real
designer.
Similarly, students confronted with dissenting opinion
about neo-Darwinism will naturally want to ask: Are there any other competing
explanations for the origin of biological form? Good science can hardly require
teachers to refuse to answer such a question. Spokes should be free to say,
“Some scientists see evidence of actual design, rather than just apparent
design, and believe this hypothesis constitutes a better explanation for
certain features of biological organisms.” Given the absence a “scientific
magisterium,” or a reigning body of scientists to decide empirical disputes by
edict, Spokes should be free to present design theory and allow students to
consider its merits. Unless some other reason for excluding it can be
established, he should feel free to teach the entire scientific controversy, as
accurately and fairly as he is able, and permit his students, as scientists in
the making, to judge for themselves.
Of course, another reason for excluding discussion of
design theory has been proffered: the claim that it violates the establishment
clause.
VI. Is It Religion? The Theory of
Intelligent
Design and the Establishment Clause
A recent law review article argues that the theory of
intelligent design should not be included in science classroom discussion
because to do so would constitute an establishment of religion. In a recent
review of the legal status of a supplementary text188 that presents the
theory of intelligent design, Jay D. Wexler states, at least for the purpose of
argument, that design theory may qualify as scientific in character.189 Nevertheless, he
argues that teaching about design would offend the Establishment Clause of the
First Amendment190 because
the theory of intelligent design constitutes a religious belief.191 Thus, he argues,
the same limitations apply to teaching design theory as apply to teaching
Judaism, Christianity, or Buddhism in the public schools.192 He notes, “[t]he
First Amendment forbids the government from establishing religion; it does not
require it to teach science.”193
This section of the Article will proceed in several
stages to refute the identification of design theory as a religion. First, we
will show that the courts have been reluctant to proffer specific legal
definitions of religion, especially ones that can be used to assign the legal
burdens of religion to institutions or entities that do not define themselves
as religious. Second, we will show that definitional criteria the courts have
enunciated, such as a test adopted by the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, do
not justify classifying the theory of intelligent design as a religion. Third,
we will show that attempts to equate the theory of intelligent design with
creation science, and thus, to extend legal judgments about the inadmissibility
of creation science to design theory, ignore legally relevant differences
between them.194 Indeed,
we will show that neither the ruling in Edwards v. Aguillard,195 nor a more
general reliance on the Lemon196
test, can offer any constitutional basis for preventing teachers from teaching
students about the theory of intelligent design in public science classrooms.
A. Defining
Religion
Just as establishing a general definition of science
has proven to be both legally and philosophically problematic, so too has the
task of finding a general legal definition of religion proved to be challenging
for the courts. Nevertheless, given the language of the Establishment Clause,
the courts require some criteria by which they can identify religion and decide
when to assign the legal benefits or burdens of religion. Indeed, unless the
courts have some working definition of religion, they cannot decide, for
example, whether an organization seeking a tax advantage available to religious
organizations (but not to others) should receive it.197 Similarly,
lacking such a definition, they cannot decide when to forbid government aid to
religious organizations or to organizations that want to use government funds
for religious purposes.198
Cases that turn on the definition of religion
typically involve a dispute brought either by someone who complains that a
state’s definition of religion is too narrow (because it does not extend to the
complainant, who wants a benefit conferred by religion)199 or too broad
(because the complainant doesn’t want a legal burden associated with
non-religious status).200
The courts have generally shown a willingness to accept a broader conception of
religion when complainants seek benefits of religious status under the law,
such as exemption from military service.201
They have tended to favor a more narrow conception of religion when considering
the assignment of legal burdens to defendants who deny being engaged in
religious activity.202 Such
cases arise when someone accuses a defendant of engaging in a religious
activity in order to impose the constitutional restrictions on the defendant
that accompany a religious designation.203
As we shall see, such accusations are rarely successful.204
Despite the obvious necessity of having some
definition of religion,205
a review of relevant cases shows that the courts have been hesitant to draw
precise boundaries.206 Indeed,
the Ninth,207 Eleventh,208 and Second209 Cir-cuits have
all rejected the invitation to craft precise definitions of religion. As the
Second Circuit Court of Appeals recognized in United States v. Kauten,210 the meaning of
“religion” as a “term is found in the history of the human race and is
incapable of compression into a few words.”211
The judges’ reluctance may derive, in part, from their recognition of the
danger of trying to make theological or philosophical distinctions in the
absence of training or authority to do so.212
Moreover, scholars have also expressed concern that in
making theological and philosophical distinctions about what constitutes
religion, and thereby extending or withholding benefits or burdens on that
basis, judges will become instruments for the favoring of one theological view
over another.213 Indeed,
different religions have different understandings of the nature of religion and
religious belief. Judgments about the nature of religion may thus necessarily
favor one religious viewpoint over another. For this reason, the courts have
been understandably hesitant to devise bright-line definitions of religion,
especially where those definitions would too easily allow courts to assign the
legal burdens of religion.214
A typical example is Peloza v. Capistrano Unified
School District.215
Peloza sued the school district that employed him, claiming that by forcing him
to teach “evolutionism” and “secular humanism” to his students, his employer
had created an “establishment of religion.”216
The court rejected his assertion, finding that neither “evolutionism [n]or
secular humanism are ‘religions’ for Establishment Clause purposes.”217 The court based
this finding on “both the dictionary definition of religion and the clear weight
of the caselaw” contradicting Peloza’s claim.218
The court also referred to the suggestion by Professor Laurence Tribe that
“anything ‘arguably non-religious’ should not be considered religious in
applying the establishment clause.”219
Similarly, in Alvarado v. City of San Jose,220 a group of
citizens brought suit against the city of San Jose, alleging that the city’s
installation of a sculpture of the Aztec god Quetzalcoatl violated the
Establishment Clause.221
The court ruled that the sculpture was not religious in nature.222 In making its
ruling, the court relied on a three-part test to define religion.223
First, a religion addresses fundamental and ultimate
questions having to do with deep and imponderable matters. Second, a religion
is comprehensive in nature; it consists of a belief-system as opposed to an
isolated teaching. Third, a religion often can be recognized by the presence of
certain formal and external signs.224
The court further clarified the test by noting that
“‘formal and external signs’” include such practices as “‘formal services,
ceremonial functions, the existence of clergy, structure and organization,
efforts at propagation, observance of holidays and other similar manifestations
associated with the traditional religions.’”225
B. Applying
the Ninth Circuit’s Test for Religion
Though the courts have generally resisted formulating
definitions of religion, the Ninth Circuit test articulated in Peloza v.
Capistrano Unified School District226
and Alvarado v. City of San Jose227
stands as a clear exception to that rule.228
Even so, this three-part test clearly provides no grounds for classifying the
theory of intelligent design as a religion.
Consider the first part: Design theory does not
attempt to address “‘fundamental and ultimate questions’” concerning “‘deep and
imponderable matters.’”229
On the contrary, design theory seeks to answer a question raised by Darwin, as
well as contemporary biologists: How did biological organisms acquire their
appearance of design? Design theory, unlike neo-Darwinism, attributes this
appearance to a designing intelligence, but it does not address the
characteristics or identity of the designing intelligence.230 Of course, design
theory is consistent with theism and adds plausibility to the classical design
arguments for the existence of God.231
But this compatibility does not make it a religious belief. As Justice Powell
wrote in his concurrence to Edwards v. Aguillard232: “[A] decision
respecting the subject matter to be taught in public schools does not violate
the Establishment Clause simply because the material to be taught ‘happens to
coincide or harmonize with the tenets of some or all religions.’”233 According to
Powell, interference by the federal courts in the decisions of local and state
educational officials is justified “only when the purpose for their decisions
is clearly religious.”234
The second part of the test identifies religion with a
comprehensive belief system “‘as opposed to an isolated teaching.’”235 Design theory
does not offer a theory of morality or metaphysics, or an opinion on the
prospects for an afterlife.236
It requires neither a belief in divine revelation nor a code of conduct; nor
does it purport to uncover the underlying meaning of the universe or to confer
esoteric knowledge upon its adherents.237
It is simply a theory about the source of the appearance of design in living
organisms.238 It is a
clear example of an “isolated teaching,” one that has no logically necessary
connections to any spiritual dogma or church institution. Design theory has no
religious pretensions. It merely tries to apply a well-established scientific
method to the analysis of biological phenomena.
The third part of the test concerns the “‘presence of
certain formal and external signs.’”239
The court provided a list of such signs, including liturgy, clergy, and
observance of holidays.240
Obviously, design theory has none of these—no sacred texts; no ordained
ministers, priests, or religious teachers; no design theory liturgies; no
design theory holidays; and no institutional structures like those of religious
groups. Design theorists have formed organizations and institutes,241 but these
resemble other academic or professional associations rather than churches or
religious institutions.
C. Do
Religious Implications Turn a Theory Into Religion?
According to the Ninth Circuit’s three-part test,
design theory should not be classified as religion. To say that, however, does
not suggest that evidence for design has no religious or metaphysical implications.
Design theory argues that a designing intelligence is responsible for the “irreducibly
complex”242 and
“information-rich” structures in biological organisms.243 Students who
believe in a creator God may, therefore, find support for their faith from the
evidence that supports design theory and may identify the designing
intelligence allegedly responsible for biological complexity with the God of
their religious belief. Alternatively, students with no religious convictions
may find that evidence of design leads them to ask theological questions and to
inquire into the identity of such a designing intelligence.
This potential for metaphysical extrapolation,
however, does not make design theory a religious doctrine. Nor is this
potential unique to design theory. Darwinism, and other materialistic origins
theories, have a similar potential. Indeed, non-religious students may find
support for agnostic or materialistic metaphysical beliefs in Darwinian theory.
Similarly, a religious student might find a materialistic world view more
plausible as a result of a scientific study of Darwinism. Darwinism, which
holds that life evolved via an undirected natural process,244 implies that
common religious beliefs about the origin of life and the nature of human life
are, if not false, then implausible. Indeed, a host of prominent neo-Darwinian
scientists—from Douglas Futuyma245
to William Provine246 to
Stephen Jay Gould247—have
insisted that Darwinism has made traditional beliefs about God and humanity
either untenable or less plausible. Consider the following statements by Gould:
• “[B]iology
took away our status as paragons created in the image of
God. . . .248
• “Before
Darwin, we thought that a benevolent God had created us.”249
• “[W]hy do
humans exist? . . . I do not think that any ‘higher’ answer
can be given . . . . We are the offspring of history,
and must establish our own paths in this most diverse and interesting of
conceivable universes—one indifferent to our suffering, and therefore offering
us maximal freedom to thrive, or to fail, in our own chosen way.”250
Contrary to the popular just-the-facts
stereotype of science, many scientific theories have larger ideological and
religious implications.251
Origins theories, in particular, raise unavoidable philosophical and religious
considerations. Theories about where the universe, life, and humanity came from
invariably affect our perspectives about human nature, morality, and ultimate
reality. As the preceding quotations have made clear, neo-Darwinian
evolutionary theory has implications for such questions.
Darwinism (in both its classical and contemporary
versions) insists that living systems organized themselves into increasingly
complex structures without assistance from a guiding intelligence.252 Chemical
evolutionary theorists likewise insist that the first life arose, without
direction, from brute chemistry.253
The Oxford zoologist Richard Dawkins has dubbed this the “blind watchmaker”
thesis.254 He, and other
leading evolutionary theorists, claim that biological evidence overwhelmingly
supports this purposeless and fully materialistic account of creation.255 Thus George
Gaylord Simpson, the leading neo-Darwinist a generation ago, could claim: “Man
is the result of a purposeless and materialistic process that did not
have him in mind. He was not planned.”256
Accordingly, many major biology texts present
evolution as a process in which a purposeful intelligence (such as God) plays
no detectable role. As Miller and Levine explain, the evolutionary process is
“random and undirected” and occurs “without plan or purpose.”257 Some texts even
state that Darwin’s theory has profoundly negative implications for theism, and
especially for its belief in the purposeful design of nature. As Douglas
Futuyma’s biology text explains: “By coupling undirected, purposeless variation
to the blind, uncaring process of natural selection, Darwin made theological or
spiritual explanations of the life processes superfluous.”258
Nevertheless, the content of a scientific theory, and
not its implications, determines its legal status in public school science
classrooms. Otherwise, the anti-theistic implications of neo-Darwinism (as
articulated by some of its chief advocates) would disqualify it from inclusion
in the curriculum. As Justice Hugo Black once asked, “[I]f the theory [of
evolution] is considered anti-religious, as the Court indicates, how can the
State be bound by the Federal Constitution to permit its teachers to advocate
such an ‘anti-religious’ doctrine to schoolchildren?”259 Of course,
Justice Black’s question was purely hypothetical, since he did not advocate
actually forbidding teachers to teach about Darwinian evolutionary theory.260 Indeed, such an
outcome would be unthinkable. Yet, if the religious (or anti-religious)
implications, rather than the specific propositional content, of theories were
at issue, then arguably neither Darwinian theory nor design theory could pass
constitutional muster. However, this result would not only undercut science
education, but it would also violate constitutional precedents. One of the few
fixed points in Establishment Clause jurisprudence during the last half-century
has been that incidental harmonies with religious beliefs do not disqualify
secular concepts under the First Amendment.261
D. Extending
Edwards v. Aguillard to Cover Design Theory?
Many critics may concede that general legal
definitions of religion (such as the 9th Circuit test) cannot establish design
as a religion for legal purposes. Nevertheless, they would classify design
theory as religion on different grounds. Rather than applying a general
definition of religion as a legal test, these critics262 have equated
design theory with religion by claiming that the issue is controlled by the
Court’s holding in Edwards v. Aguillard.263
In the early 1980s, creationists in Louisiana sought
to introduce scientific creationism into the Louisiana public school system. As
a result, the Louisiana Legislature passed a law titled the “Balanced Treatment
for Creation-Science and Evolution-Science in Public School Instruction (the
“Act”).264 The Act did not
require teaching either creationism or evolution, but did require that when one
theory was taught, the other must be taught as well.265
Several parents and concerned citizens challenged the
constitutionality of the Act in federal court.266
They argued that the Act violated the First Amendment’s Establishment Clause,
which prohibits the government from officially endorsing a religious belief.267 The State
responded that the Act did not violate the First Amendment because it had the
legitimate secular purpose of strengthening and broadening the academic freedom
of teachers.268 The
district court and the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit, however, found
that the State’s actual purpose was to promote the religious doctrine of
creationism (known also as creation science).269
The Court, in a majority opinion written by Justice
Brennan, ruled that the Act constituted an unconstitutional infringement on the
Establishment Clause of the First Amendment,270
based on the Lemon test.271
This test, which was first enunciated by the Court in Lemon v. Kurtzman,272 consists of three
prongs:
(1) The
government's action must have a secular purpose;
(2) The
government’s action must not have the primary effect of either advancing or
inhibiting religion; and
(3) The
government's action must not result in an “excessive entanglement” of the
government and religion.273
If government action or legislation violates any of
these three prongs, it will be deemed unconstitutional under the Establishment
Clause.274 The first of
these prongs has become known as the “purpose prong.”275 The Court found
that the Act violated the purpose prong and was, therefore, unconstitutional
for several reasons.276
First, since the legislative history of the Act constantly referenced the
religious views of the legislators, the Court became suspicious of the State’s
claim that the Act’s purpose was to advance academic freedom.277 Second, the Court
found that the intent of the legislator who drafted the Act was to narrow the
science curriculum in order to favor a particular religious belief (i.e., the creation
account as found in the book of Genesis).278
In support of this finding the Court noted that the Act’s sponsor actually
preferred that “neither [creationism nor evolution] be taught.”279 The Court,
therefore, concluded that the purpose of the Act was to limit, rather than
promote, academic freedom and science education.280
The Court also found that the Act did not grant
teachers any new “flexibility [in teaching science] that they did not already
possess.”281 The Court
noted that no Louisiana law barred the teaching of any scientific theory about
biological origins.282 Since
teachers were already free to teach scientific alternatives to Darwinian
evolution, the Court reasoned that the Act did not expand the academic freedom
already enjoyed by teachers in Louisiana.283
Having rejected the State’s proffered reason for the
Act, the Court then uncovered what it regarded as the true intent of the
Louisiana law: the promotion of a particular religious view. The Court found
that the Act had a “discriminatory preference” for the teaching of creationism
because it required the production of curriculum guides for creationism.284 Further, it found
that only creationism was protected by certain sections of the Act, and that
the Act undercut truly comprehensive science instruction by limiting the
theories of origins that teachers could teach to just two: evolution and
creationism.285
In deciding against the Act, the Court was careful to
point out that its decision in no way excluded the teaching of other scientific
theories about biological origins.286
Likewise, the Court left the door open to scientific critiques of Darwinian
evolution.287 In an
illuminating section of the majority opinion, the Court even stated that
teaching a variety of scientific theories about origins “might be validly done
with the clear secular intent of enhancing the effectiveness of science
instruction.”288 However,
the Court could not discern such an intent in the legislative history of Act.
Instead, it determined that the primary purpose of the Act was to promote a
particular religious doctrine, thereby violating the Establishment Clause.289
Many have assumed that the reasoning in Edwards
can be extended to cover curricular debates about the admissibility of teaching
about design theory. Indeed, many have argued that the theory of intelligent
design and creation science are effectively indistinguishable for both
scientific and legal purposes.290
Since the court in Edwards ruled that creation science promoted a
religious viewpoint, many have concluded that teaching public school students
about design theory also illicitly promotes a religious viewpoint in the public
schools.291
E. The
Legal Differences Between Creation Science and Design Theory
Despite claims to the contrary, design theory and
scientific creationism differ in propositional content, method of inquiry, and,
thus, in legal status. Recall that in Edwards v. Aguillard292 the Court decided
against the legality of scientific creationism because it constituted an
advancement of religion.293
The Court reached this decision in large part because the propositional content
of scientific creationism closely mirrors the creation narrative in the book of
Genesis.294 While
philosophers of science now agree that the scientific status of an idea
does not depend upon its source, the Court seems to have assumed that the legal
status of an idea—and therefore the legal status of any curriculum based on
that idea—does depend on its source. Thus, given the Court’s reasoning in Edwards,
the teaching of “creation science” remains legally problematic.
Nevertheless, the Court’s decision does not apply to
design theory because design theory is not based upon a religious text or
doctrine. Design theory begins with the data that scientists observe in the
laboratory and nature, and attempts to explain such data based on what we know
about the patterns that generally indicate intelligent causes. For design
theorists, the conclusion of design constitutes an inference from biological
data, not a deduction from religious authority.
Furthermore, the propositional content of design
theory differs significantly from that of scientific creationism. Scientific
creationism is committed to the following propositions:
(1) There was a sudden creation of the universe,
energy, and life from nothing.
(2) Mutations and natural selection are insufficient
to bring about the development of all living kinds from a single organism.
(3) Changes in the originally created kinds of plants
and animals occur only within fixed limits.
(4) There is a separate ancestry for humans and apes.
(5) The earth’s geology can be explained via
catastrophism, primarily by the occurrence of a worldwide flood.
(6) The earth and living kinds had a relatively recent
origin (on the order of ten thousand years ago).295
These six tenets taken jointly define scientific
creationism for legal purposes. The Court in Edwards ruled that, taken
jointly, this group of propositions may not be taught in public school science
classrooms—at least not where they are animated by the religious purpose of the
Louisiana Legislature.296
Nevertheless, the Court left the door open to some of these tenets being
discussed individually.297
Design theory, on the other hand, asserts the
following:
(1) High information content298 (or specified
complexity) and irreducible complexity299
constitute strong indicators or hallmarks of past intelligent design.
(2) Biological systems have a high information content
(or specified complexity) and utilize subsystems that manifest irreducible
complexity.300
(3) Naturalistic mechanisms or undirected causes do
not suffice to explain the origin of information (specified complexity) or
irreducible complexity.301
(4) Therefore, intelligent design constitutes the best
explanation for the origin of information and irreducible complexity in
biological systems.302
A comparison of these two lists demonstrates clearly
that design theory and scientific creationism differ markedly in content.
Clearly, then, they do not derive from the same source. Thus, the Court’s
ruling in Edwards does not apply to design theory and can provide no
grounds for excluding discussion of intelligent design from the public school
science curriculum.
F. A
Residual Lemon Objection
Some might acknowledge these differences and still
claim that teaching about design theory constitutes an advancement of religion.
For example, it could be argued that the theory of intelligent design suffers
from its own inability to meet the Lemon test, which was the basis of
the Court’s decision in Edwards. Just as the Balanced Treatment Act
advocating the teaching of creation science failed to meet the Lemon
test because the Court found that it expressed a religious and not a secular
purpose, one might argue that teaching about design theory would run afoul of
the Lemon test because advocates for its inclusion in the curriculum
have religious, rather than secular, reasons for promoting it. Indeed, as noted
above, many advocates of contemporary design theory openly acknowledge that
evidence for design in nature may have theistic implications.303 Some also see
Darwinian evolution as an implicit challenge to a theistic worldview.304 Viewing the issue
as they do, some advocates for the inclusion of design theory in the
curriculum, including teachers, school board members, or parents, may view
teaching about the theory of intelligent design as a means of defending, or
even promoting, their theistic beliefs.305
Thus, one might argue that such religiously-motivated advocacy disqualifies
design theory from consideration in the curriculum under the first prong of the
Lemon test.
Nevertheless, even the presence of
religiously-motivated advocacy for design theory in the curriculum does not
warrant its exclusion under the first prong of the Lemon test for
several reasons. First, the Lemon test does not require that advocates
of a government action have no religious motivations, only that a
government action itself embodies some secular purpose.306 Recall that the
majority in Edwards rejected the proffered secular purpose of the
legislature—the claim that the Balanced Treatment Act (the “Act”) sought to
promote academic freedom.307
It found this claim implausible on the grounds that teachers already had the
academic freedom to teach alternative scientific viewpoints.308 Failing to find a
plausible secular purpose for the Act, the Court concluded that the sole
motivation of those advocating the Act must have been to advance a religious
viewpoint.309 By
contrast, in the hypothetical we have posed, John Spokes wants to improve
science education and to expose his students to the full range of opinion that
exists among scientists about biological origins. Thus, his teaching is clearly
motivated by a secular purpose. Moreover, even if Spokes had a religious as
well as a scientific purpose for wanting to expose his students to the theory
of intelligent design, or even if some of his supporters on the school board
had such a purpose, his proposed pedagogy would still meet the first prong of
the Lemon test. Again, the Lemon test does not require that a
government action (such as teaching a public school science class) have only
a secular purpose, but that it have a secular purpose.310 Insofar as Spokes
seeks to inform his students about a variety of scientific interpretations of
existing biological data, or to enhance his students’ critical thinking skills,
or to expose students to the method of multiple competing hypotheses in the
historical sciences, his pedagogy clearly embodies a secular purpose.
Second, since the Edwards decision, the
constitutional standard for deciding the permissibility of
religiously-motivated speech has changed. In Rosenberger v. Rector and
Visitors of the Univ. of Virginia,311
the Court permitted an evangelical Christian student publication group to
receive state funds for an expressly religious publication, despite the claim
that such funding would violate the Establishment Clause.312 Since other
student groups had received state funds for promoting their viewpoints, the
Court found that the exclusion of a religious viewpoint because of its content
would constitute viewpoint discrimination.313
Indeed, the Court struck down the university’s refusal to fund the religious
group as a violation of the First Amendment’s guarantee of viewpoint
neutrality.314
Yet if the Court has ruled that the constitution
allows funding religiously-motivated speech—indeed speech of an explicitly
religious character—in order to prevent viewpoint discrimination, then clearly
the constitution must permit other forms of religiously-motivated expression,
especially those forms of expression that address scientific evidence and are
(at most) only religious in their implications. Thus, a teacher or school board
that chooses to include presentations about design theory in the curriculum in
order to prevent an imbalance in the presentation of scientific perspectives on
biological origins, would enact a secular purpose every bit as compelling as
the one the state university was required to demonstrate in Rosenberger.315
In any case, no constitutional test has established
design theory as a religious viewpoint, much less an establishment of religion.
Nor, strictly speaking, can the Lemon test make such determinations.
Instead, the courts use the Lemon test to determine when a government
action involving religion constitutes an unacceptable advancement of that
religion.316 In Edwards,
the Court simply assumed that creation science constituted a religious belief
because of its resemblance to the creation narrative in the Book of Genesis,
and then sought to determine whether the Louisiana Balanced Treatment Act
constituted an illicit advancement of that religious belief.317 Yet, as argued
above, similar grounds do not exist for classifying design theory as a
religious belief. Indeed, given its basis in scientific evidence, and its
failure to meet other legal criteria of religion, such as those articulated in
the 9th Circuit test, every presumption militates against such an
identification.
G. Back
to Spokes
Spokes need not worry about a legal challenge to his
decision to expose students to scientific criticism of Darwinian evolution. As
the Court’s ruling in Edwards made explicit, exposing students to
critiques of Darwinian theory does not constitute an advancement of religion.318 Indeed, the
refusal to permit any criticism of Darwinism resembles nothing so much as an
enshrinement of the very “orthodoxy” that Justice Jackson once declared
inconsistent with our constitution.319
Spokes should also have no compunctions about what
might seem a more controversial action, namely, his teaching students about
alternatives to Darwinism,320
including the theory of intelligent design. Given the larger theistic
implications of design, Spokes might fear censure under the Establishment
Clause. Yet if Spokes’ actions advance the secular purpose of improving science
education, then whatever support design theory might provide to religious
belief does not compromise its legal status. In any case, as a good science
teacher Spokes can encourage students not to limit consideration of the
scientific evidence based on their metaphysical presuppositions, whether
theological or naturalistic.321
If a student raises the metaphysical implications of a theory as an argument
for or against its acceptance, then Spokes can encourage students to address
the evidential merits of the competing theories.322 On the other
hand, to deny discussion of an important scientific issue because it causes
metaphysical discomfort to some would in effect grant a heckler’s veto. The
Court has refused to do this.323
In his biology class Spokes can present his students with multiple competing
hypotheses, such as classical Darwinism, the neo-Darwinist synthesis,
punctuated equilibrium, and design theory. By allowing students to evaluate the
evidential merits of each theory, Spokes eschews indoctrination in favor of
liberal education. Given the metaphysical implications in play, such a pedagogy
more closely honors the intent of the Establishment Clause than the one-sided
and dogmatic mode of presentation demanded by the National Center for Science
Education and the National Academy of Sciences.324
VII. Is It Speech? Design Theory
and Viewpoint Discrimination
Suppose the administrators and school board members,
after listening to Spokes’ presentation, decide to endorse Spokes’s curricular
changes, including his decision to teach students about the scientific case for
design. Would they face legal exposure for doing so? Given the controversy
associated with these issues, and the widespread (if erroneous) belief that all
non-materialistic alternatives to Darwinism (such as design theory) constitute
religion, many school boards might assume that they should permit teachers to
teach only about Darwinism and forbid any discussion of alternative theories,
especially design theory. Indeed, given widespread misconceptions about the
bearing of the Establishment Clause on the biology curriculum, school boards
and administrators might assume that restricting teachers in this way
represents the safest course legally. However, the law not only permits Spokes
to present alternatives, but it now forbids publicly funded viewpoint
discrimination, with certain exceptions that do not apply to this controversy.
Moreover, recent cases have provided a strong reaffirmation of the primary
responsibility and authority reposed in school boards to decide upon their own
curriculum:
Someone must fix the curriculum of any school, public
or private. In the case of a public school, in our opinion, it is far better
public policy, absent a valid statutory directive on the subject, that the
makeup of the curriculum be entrusted to the local school authorities who are
in some sense responsible, rather than to the teachers, who would be
responsible only to the judges, had they a First Amendment right to participate
in the makeup of the curriculum.325
Thus, if a teacher (with the school board’s support)
elects to broaden the curriculum , the law not only allows, but encourages,
such a course of action.
A more difficult case might arise if a teacher wants
to broaden his curriculum as Spokes has decided to do, but his school board or
administration opposes his pedagogy. Here the authority of the school board to
decide curriculum collides with the academic freedom of the teacher. What does
the law, and particularly the recent rulings about viewpoint discrimination,
have to say in such situations? Do Spokes’s proposed changes constitute legally
protected speech, or does the authority of the school board trump Spokes’s
academic freedom?
Several precedents suggest that Spokes’s changes do
constitute legally protected speech and that even the legitimate rights of
school boards to set curricular guidelines do not supersede Spokes’s academic
freedom in this matter. As noted, the law has strongly affirmed the authority
of school boards to establish the curricular guidelines in their school
districts. Nevertheless, that authority is not unlimited. As the Court
said in Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School District:326
First Amendment rights, applied in light of the
special characteristics of the school environment, are available to teachers
and students. It can hardly be argued that either students or teachers shed
their constitutional rights to freedom of speech or expression at the
schoolhouse gate. This has been the unmistakable holding of this Court for
almost 50 years.327
Indeed, addressing a situation in which a school board
claimed the unfettered right to determine the content of a school library, the
Court made the following comments:
Petitioners [the school board] rightly possess
significant discretion to determine the content of their school libraries. But
that discretion may not be exercised in a narrowly partisan or political
manner. If a Democratic school board, motivated by party affiliation, ordered
the removal of all books written by or in favor of Republicans, few would doubt
that the order violated the constitutional rights of the students denied access
to those books. The same conclusion would surely apply if an all-white school
board, motivated by racial animus, decided to remove all books authored by
blacks or advocating racial equality and integration. Our Constitution does not
permit the official suppression of ideas. Thus whether petitioners’
removal of books from their school libraries denied respondents their First
Amendment rights depends upon the motivation behind petitioners’ actions. If
petitioners intended by their removal decision to deny respondents
access to ideas with which petitioners disagreed, and if this intent was the
decisive factor in petitioners’ [school board’s] decision, then petitioners
have exercised their discretion in violation of the Constitution. To permit
such intentions to control official actions would be to encourage the precise
sort of officially prescribed orthodoxy unequivocally condemned in Barnette.328
Such rulings suggest that school boards that allow
teachers (or their libraries) to present only one side of a controversial issue
expose themselves to risk of litigation, especially if their decision to do so
is “intended . . . to deny . . . access
to ideas with which [they] disagreed.”329
A. The
Rosenberger Revolution
For many years, lawyers and others have assumed that
the Establishment Clause, preventing state aid to religion, superseded the
constitutional guarantees of free speech. Nevertheless, the United States
Supreme Court has more recently emphasized that the First Amendment prohibits
the government from regulating speech “based on its substantive content or the
message it conveys,”330
even where the content of the speech is religious.331 Indeed, the Court
has described this view of the First Amendment as “axiomatic.”332 The Court has
strongly affirmed this principle in several opinions dealing with issues as
diverse as civil rights meetings,333
the funding of a religiously-based student publication at a public university,334 and the use of a
public school auditorium by a religious group to show a film.335 These rulings
bear significantly on deciding the relative priority of, and the relationship
between, a school board’s right to determine curriculum content and a teacher’s
right to academic freedom.
In the most recent case on viewpoint discrimination, Rosenberger
v. Rector and Visitors of the University of Virginia,336 the Supreme Court
strongly reaffirmed its previous holdings and held that viewpoint
discrimination arising from a misplaced fear of violating the Establishment
Clause is itself unconstitutional.337
Rosenberger, a student at a state university, objected to the university’s
refusal to grant to his organization’s newspaper the same financial subsidy
that other campus organizations had received.338
The university defended its policy by citing the newspaper’s evangelical
Christian perspective. The university held that any funding of the paper would
endorse a religious viewpoint and would thus violate the Constitution.339 The Supreme Court
rejected this argument, holding that if a public institution opens a forum for
free speech, it cannot then censor the forum based solely on the viewpoint of
the speech expressed.340
The Court noted that viewpoint discrimination “is
presumed to be unconstitutional.”341
Nevertheless, it argued, when the government itself targets speech simply
because of its content “the violation of the First Amendment is all the more
blatant.”342
Consequently, the Court found that the government must “abstain” from
content-based speech restrictions when the “ideology or the opinion or
perspective of the speaker is the rationale for the restriction.”343 The Court
affirmed that the government may not engage in content-based suppression of
speech even when the public forum where the speech occurs was created by the
government in the first place.344
The Court’s position allowed two exceptions. First,
the government may control access to a nonpublic forum based “on subject matter
and speaker identity” if the government’s action is reasonable considering the
forum’s purpose and if the action is viewpoint neutral.345 This means that
the government can supress speech in a nonpublic forum if the speaker wants to
discuss “a topic not encompassed within the purpose of the forum,”346 or the speaker is
outside of the special class for whom the forum was created.347 Second, if the
government is charged with viewpoint discrimination, it can clear itself of
that charge by showing that to permit the speech in question would violate the
Establishment Clause.348
Neither of these exceptions applies to Spokes’s plan
to teach his students about design theory. The Court showed itself quite
willing to grant wide latitude for even explicitly religious speech or viewpoints,
in Rosenberger, when it articulated an Establishment Clause exception to
the general prohibition against viewpoint discrimination.349 If the Court had
meant to include all religious speech within this exception, it clearly could
not have reached the decision it did in Rosenberger. In any case, as
already argued, teaching about design theory does not constitute an
establishment of religion.
Moreover, the overwhelming majority of public schools
(including presumably Spokes’s) already address the subject of biological
origins in their science curriculum. While the courts have limited the free
speech rights of teachers in the public school context,350 teachers do have
the right to choose supplementary material that is appropriate to the subjects
they have been mandated to teach. Likewise, students may certainly learn about
current ideas relevant to the subjects they are studying.351 Further, the
Supreme Court has found that teachers, students, and parents have a “liberty
interest” under the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause not to be
prevented from studying certain subjects.352
A critical aspect of this liberty interest is academic freedom. Academic
freedom allows teachers to present appropriate material to their students
without fear of censorship or retribution from the government. Teachers not
only need academic freedom to teach effectively, but students need it to
explore and develop new ideas. Without academic freedom, education becomes
indoctrination.
The Supreme Court recognized this fundamental right to
academic freedom in Epperson v. Arkansas.353 In that case, the
Court struck down an Arkansas statute that restricted the teachings of
biological origins.354 The
statute prohibited, with criminal sanction, the teaching of the theory of
evolution in the public schools of that state.355
A teacher challenged the statute claiming that it violated her academic
freedom.356 The Supreme
Court, in rejecting the Arkansas law as unconstitutional, strongly upheld the
academic freedom of teachers in the public schools.357
The Court found that the First Amendment’s guarantees
apply to our school systems, where they are “essential to safeguard the
fundamental values of freedom of speech and inquiry and of belief.”358 The Court made
clear that “the First Amendment ‘does not tolerate laws that cast a pall of
orthodoxy over the classroom.’”359
Most significantly, the Court found that the government’s power to determine
school curricula does not give it the power to prevent “the teaching of a
scientific theory or doctrine where that prohibition is based upon reasons that
violate the First Amendment.”360
The Court even went so far as to assert that “[i]t is much too late to argue
that the State may impose upon the teachers in its schools any conditions that
it chooses, however restrictive they may be of constitutional guarantees.”361 The same freedoms
that allow teachers to present Darwinian evolutionary theory would seem to
allow teachers to teach students about the theory of intelligent design, even
if their school boards oppose their pedagogy.
While public schools are not public fora per
se, they are publicly funded places where ideas are exchanged.362 Thus, if public
schools or other governmental agencies bar teachers from teaching about design
theory but allow teachers to teach neo-Darwinism, they will undermine free
speech and foster viewpoint discrimination. At the very least, the government
has no affirmative duty to censor teachers who attempt to present alternative
viewpoints on scientific issues. Instead, strictly speaking, the Constitution
prohibits such censorship or the regulation of speech “in ways that favor some
viewpoints or ideas at the expense of others.”363
B. Edwards
v. Aguillard Revisited
Some might argue, of course, that court strictures
against viewpoint discrimination apply only to “soft” subjects in the
humanities such as politics, law, and religion that admit many differing
interpretations. Since, they argue, the “hard” sciences do not involve
significant subjectivity in interpretation, controversy plays no legitimate
role in scientific discourse or education. Thus, teachers have no need to teach
both sides of controversial issues in science and school boards have no reason
to respect the right of teachers who do so. Such an objection, however, not
only belies a false and antiquated positivistic philosophy of science (indeed,
the history of science shows many arguments between scientists about the
correct interpretation of data), it also contradicts the explicit and specific
ruling of the Court concerning the scientific controversy over biological
origins.
As noted above, in Edwards v. Aguillard,364 the Court
affirmed the academic freedom of teachers in the public schools to present a
variety of scientific theories about biological origins.365 Indeed, the Court
struck down the Louisiana Balanced Treatment Act in large part based on
academic freedom considerations.366
Recall that the Court found disingenuous the Act’s proffered secular purpose of
promoting academic freedom, and that it expressed concern about several
specific provisions of the Act that appeared to limit such freedom.367 In rejecting the
proffered purpose of the Act, the Court carefully reaffirmed the academic
freedom of teachers to teach alternative scientific (as opposed to Bible-based)
theories of origins.368
The Court noted that the Louisiana law did not give teachers any more
flexibility in teaching about scientific origins theories than they had before
the passage of the law.369
It noted that Louisiana had no statute that prevented teachers from presenting
any scientific theory regarding biological or human origins.370 The Court’s
language on this point is both instructive and decisive:
We do not imply that a legislature could never require
that scientific critiques of prevailing scientific theories be taught. Indeed,
the Court acknowledged in Stone that its decision forbidding the posting
of the Ten Commandments did not mean that no use could ever be made of the Ten
Commandments, or that the Ten Commandments played an exclusively religious role
in the history of Western Civilization. In a similar way, teaching a variety of
scientific theories about the origins of humankind to schoolchildren might be
validly done with the clear secular intent of enhancing the effectiveness of
science instruction.371
Thus, far from placing its imprimatur on Darwinism as
the only permissible scientific theory of biological origins, Edwards
clearly supports the principle of academic freedom in science education.372 Further, the Edwards
case, viewed in the context of recent rulings on viewpoint discrimination,
suggests that science teachers, every bit as much as other kinds of teachers,
have the academic freedom to structure their presentations of controversial
issues to avoid discrimination based on the content of the ideas in question,
that is, to avoid viewpoint discrimination.
Thus, following Edwards, John Spokes certainly
has the academic freedom to present the scientific weaknesses of Darwinism to
his students without fear of running afoul of the Establishment Clause. As the
Court itself stated, it did not want its ruling in Edwards to be
construed as a ban on teaching “scientific critiques of prevailing scientific
theories.”373 Further,
nothing in the Edwards decision justifies excluding consideration of
design theory in the biology curriculum, unless it could be established that
design theory like creation science constitutes a religious belief.374 Quite the
contrary, the Court made clear that “teaching a variety of scientific theories
about the origins of humankind to schoolchildren might be validly done with the
clear secular intent of enhancing the effectiveness of science instruction.”375 Thus, following Edwards
and Rosenberger, Spokes’s proposed curricular changes do give every
indication of being constitutionally protected speech. Provided that his school
board has already directed him to teach about the general subject of biological
origins, Spokes should have the freedom to define how specifically he will do
so in accord with his own professional judgment about the merits of relevant
scientific ideas, and in accord with court dictates about the dangers of
viewpoint discrimination. Indeed, Rosenberger suggests that a school
board would face far more exposure to litigation by preventing Spokes from
implementing his changes than by allowing him to do so. Certainly, a school
district that forced a teacher to affirm the truth of Darwinism as a condition
of employment would enshrine the very type of "officially prescribed
orthodoxy" condemned by the Court in Barnette.376 A school board
that refused to permit criticism of Darwinism would violate the principles
expressed in Tinker377
and Pico.378 But a
school board that encouraged an open discussion of the issue, consistent with
the best scientific evidence, would reduce the likelihood of litigation by any
party.
VIII. Conclusion
Until recently, the Darwinian perspective has enjoyed
a monopoly over the curriculum in public school biology classes. Nevertheless,
a number of factors have undermined the basis for that monopoly. First,
dissenting scientific opinion about the sufficiency of the neo-Darwinian
mechanism as an explanation for the origin of apparent design has broken the
Darwinian hegemony in the scientific world. Second, within the philosophy of
science, the failure of demarcation arguments has meant that both Darwinian
evolutionary theory and design theory now enjoy equivalent methodological
status, thereby denying any legal basis for excluding opposing theories from
consideration. New constitutional precedents have also changed the context of
this curriculum debate. In 1986, Edwards v. Aguillard379 affirmed the
right of teachers to discuss alternative scientific theories of origin in their
classrooms. In addition, subsequent cases such as Rosenberger have made
it more difficult to use the Establishment Clause to limit academic freedom and
the rights of free expression.
These changes have begun to affect public perceptions
of the curricular debate. For example, recently in Melvindale, Michigan, a
Detroit suburb, the school board voted to purchase a number of books (including
Michael Behe’s Darwin’s Black Box) that detail specifically scientific
challenges to standard materialistic theories of evolution.380 This seemingly
innocuous action provoked the National Center for Science Education (“NCSE”), a
Darwinist lobby in Berkeley, California, to issue a creationism “alert” on its
website. NCSE director Eugenie Scott has warned that the inclusion of books
such as Behe’s would have a chilling effect on science education.381 But such hysteria
not only betrays the fear that always accompanies a loss of cultural control,
but represents a clear attempt to suppress controversy rather than to enlist it
in the service of science education, as the law not only allows but would now
encourage.
When school boards or biology teachers such as our
hypothetical John Spokes take the initiative to teach, rather than suppress, the
controversy as it exists in the scientific world, school board lawyers should
encourage, rather than resist, this more open and more dialectical approach.
Indeed, the time has come for school boards to resist threats of litigation
from those who would censor teachers like Spokes, and to defend their efforts
to expand student access to evidence and information about this timely and
compelling controversy.
This article is reprinted (with modest corrections
and updating) from the Utah Law Review. For further information or to contact the
authors, please contact The Discovery Institute, 206-292-0401, or visit our
website at www.discovery.org |
*Professor of Law, Gonzaga University School of Law,
Spokane, WA. B.A., Stanford University, 1971; J.D., Yale Law School, 1979.
**Associate Professor of Philosophy, Whitworth College;
Director, Center for the Renewal of Science and Culture, Discovery Institute,
Seattle, WA. B.A., Whitworth College, 1980; Ph.D., Cambridge University, 1991.
***Instructor, Central Washington University. B.A.,
Western Washington University, 1992; J.D., Gonzaga University School of Law,
1997.
1529 F. Supp. 1255 (E.D. Ark. 1982).
2482 U.S. 578 (1987).
3See John
Gibeaut, Evolution of a Controversy, A.B.A.
J., Nov. 1999, at 50, 50–55.
4Throughout this article we will refer to this view as
“Darwinian” or “Darwinist.” Although in this article we sometimes carefully
distinguish between classical Darwinian, contemporary neo-Darwinian and
chemical evolutionary theories, we also use the term “Darwinian” or “Darwinist”
to refer to all purely naturalistic theories of evolution—indeed, those that
deny any role for a designing intelligence in the history of life. As will be
discussed in greater detail below, the central feature of a Darwinist theory is
that it regards the apparent design of living things as merely apparent. Moreover,
the term “creationism” is misleading because it suggests that those who are
opposed to Darwinism base their opposition on a literal reading of the Book of
Genesis. See discussion infra Part V.A.
5Kenneth R. Miller & Joseph
Levine, Biology 658 (4th ed. 1998).
6See Charles Darwin, The Origin of Species
130, 130–72 (Penguin Books 1968).
7Francisco J. Ayala, Darwin's Revolution, in
Creative Evolution 1, 4–5 (John
H. Campbell & J. William Schopf eds. 1994).
8See Jonathan
Wells, Haeckel’s Embryos & Evolution: Setting the Record Straight,
61 Am. Biology Tchr. 345, 345–49
(1999); Gordon C. Mills et al., Origin of Life & Evolution in Biology
Textbooks—A Critique, 55 Am. Biology
Tchr. 78, 78–83 (1993).
9Jonathan Wells, Icons of
Evolution (2000).
10See infra
note 73 and accompanying text.
11See Keith
Stewart Thomson, Marginalia: The Meanings of Evolution, Am. Scientist, Sept.-Oct. 1982, at 529,
529–31.
12Indeed, he finds that many distinguished biologists
(e.g., Stuart Kauffman, Rudolf Raff, George Miklos, James Valentine) openly
acknowledge that small-scale “micro-evolutionary” changes cannot be
extrapolated to explain large-scale “macro-evolutionary” innovation. As one
group of scientists put it, natural selection can explain “the survival,
but not the arrival, of the fittest.” Scott Gilbert et al., Resynthesizing
Evolutionary and Developmental Biology, 173 Developmental Biology 357, 361 (1996).
13Michael J. Behe, Darwin’s Black
Box (1996).
14See National Academy of Science, Teaching About
Evolution and the Nature of Science 4 (1998):
Those who oppose the teaching of evolution in public
schools sometimes ask that teachers present “the evidence against evolution.”
However, there is no debate within the scientific community over whether
evolution occurred, and there is no evidence that evolution has not occurred.
Some of the details of how evolution occurs are still being investigated. But
scientists continue to debate only the particular mechanisms that result in
evolution, not the overall accuracy of evolution as the explanation of life’s history.
15The National Association of Biology Teachers issued the
following statement on teaching evolution:
The same examination, pondering and possible revision
have firmly established evolution as an important natural process explained by
valid scientific principles, and clearly differentiate and separate science
from various kinds of nonscientific ways of knowing, including those with a
supernatural basis such as creationism. Whether called “creation science,”
“scientific creationism,” “intelligent-design theory,” “young-earth theory” or
some other synonym, creation beliefs have no place in the science classroom.
Explanations employing non naturalistic or supernatural events, whether or not
explicit reference is made to a supernatural being, are outside the realm of
science and not part of a valid science curriculum. Evolutionary theory, indeed
all of science, is necessarily silent on religion and neither refutes nor
supports the existence of a deity or deities.
Id. app. C. at
129.
16See id. (“The
Commission on Science Education of the American Association for the Advancement
of Science, is vigorously opposed to attempts by some boards of education, and
other groups to require that religious accounts of creation be taught in
science classes.”).
17John Angus Campbell, Intelligent Design, Darwinism,
and the Philosophy of Public Education, 1 Rhetoric
& Pub. Aff. 469, 487 (1998).
18A recent article describes one such case. See
Gibeaut, supra note 3, at 50–55. For an additional case, see Daniel J.
Pinchot, Moon Mulls Biblical Biology Three Years After Suit, Board Wants to
Get Creation in Classes, Pittsburgh
Post-Gazette, Aug. 29, 1997, at B-1. More recently, a biology teacher
was reassigned because he taught intelligent design as part of his treatment of
the origins issue. See Marjorie Coeyman, Evolution Gets Dismissed
from Some Classes, Christian Sci.
Monitor, August 16, 1999, at 1.
19See Creationist
Book to Be Used in Burlington—Biology Teacher Questions Evolutionary Theory,
Seattle Times, June 14, 1999, at
B3; Barbara Galloway, Group Asks Alternative to Theory of Evolution;
Louisville Activists Say Darwin Camp Has Monopoly, Akron Beacon J., February 13, 1995, at A1; Laurie Goodstein, Scientists
Take New Look at Creationism, Houston
Chron., January 10, 1998, at 1; Jennifer Juarez Robles & Matt Helms,
Schools Consider Creationism, Detroit
Free Press, November 11, 1997, at 1B; Andrea Schoellkopf, Proposed
Science Curriculum Would Allow Creationism, Albuquerque J., October 29, 1997, at 1.
20See Plato, The Laws 279 (A.E. Taylor
trans., 1969).
21See Cicero, De Natura Deorum 217 (H.
Rackham trans., Harvard Univ. Press 1933).
22Aquinas used the argument from design as one of his
proofs for the existence of God. See John
Hick, Arguments for the Existence of God 1 (1971).
23See Neal C.
Gillespie, Natural History, Natural Theology, and Social Order: John Ray and
the Newtonian Ideology, 20 J. Hist.
Biology 1, passim (1987).
24See Johannes Kepler, Harmonies of the World
170, 240 (Charles Glen Wallis trans., Prometheus Books 1995) (1619); Johannes Kepler, Mysterium Cosmographicum [The
Secret of the Universe] 93–103 (A.M. Duncan trans., Arabis Books, Inc.
1981) (1596); . Kepler’s belief that the work of God is evident in nature is
illustrated by his statement in the Harmonies of the World that God “by the
light of nature promote[s] in us the desire for the light of grace, that by its
means [God] mayest transport us into the light of glory.” Kepler, Harmonies of the World, at 240.
See also Morris Kline,
Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty 39 (1980) (‘The strength of
Copernicus’s and Kepler’s conviction that God must have designed the world
harmoniously and simply can be judged by the objections with which they had to
contend.”).
25See John Ray, The Wisdom of God Manifested in the
Works of the Creation (3d ed. 1701).
26See Robert Boyle, Selected Philosophical Papers of
Robert Boyle 172 (M.A. Stewart ed. 1979).
27Newton’s Principia Motte’s
Translation Revised 543–44 (Andrew Motte
trans. & Florian Cajori rev. 1934) (1686).
28Sir Isaac Newton, Opticks 369–70 (Dover Publications 1952).
29See William Paley, Natural Theology passim
(1803).
30For a discussion of this methodological shift, see Neil C. Gillespie, Charles Darwin and the
Problem of Creation passim (1979).
31The effort to explain biological organisms was
reinforced by a trend in science to provide fully naturalistic accounts for
other phenomena such as the precise configuration of the planets in the solar
system (Laplace) and the origin of geological features (Lyell and Hutton). It
was also reinforced (and in large part made possible) by an emerging
positivistic tradition in science that increasingly sought to exclude appeals
to supernatural or intelligent causes from science by definition. See
id.
32See Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species
481–82 (Harvard Univ. Press 1964).
33See Peter J. Bowler, Theories of Human Evolution: A Century of
Debate, 1844-1944, at 44–50 (1986). Natural selection, as Darwin well
understood, could accom-plish nothing without a steady supply of genetic
variation, the ultimate source of new biological structure. Nevertheless, both
the blending theory of inheritance that Darwin had assumed and the classical
Mendelian genetics that soon replaced it, implied limitations on the amount of
genetic variability available to natural selection. This in turn implied limits
on the amount of novel structure that natural selection could produce.
34See id. passim.
35 [T]he fact of
evolution was not generally accepted until a theory had been put forward to
suggest how evolution had occurred, and in particular how organisms could
become adapted to their environment; in the absence of such a theory,
adaptation suggested design, and so implied a creator. It was this need which
Darwin's theory of natural selection satisfied.
John Maynard Smith, The Theory
of Evolution 30 (Penguin Books 3d ed.
1975).
36Ernst Mayr, Foreword to Michael Ruse, Darwinism Defended, xi-xii (1982).
37“There is absolutely no disagreement among professional
biologists on the fact that evolution has
occurred. . . . But the theory of how evolution
occurs is quite another matter, and is the subject of intense dispute.” Douglas
Futuyma, Evolution as Fact and Theory, 56 Bios 3, 8 (1985). Of course, to admit that natural selection
cannot explain the appearance of design is in effect to admit that it has
failed to perform the role that is claimed for it as a “designer substitute.”
38Niles Eldredge, An Ode to Adaptive Transformation,
296 Nature 508 (1982).
39Stephen Jay Gould, Is a New and General Theory of
Evolution Emerging? 6 Paleobiology
119, 119–20 (1980).
40One of the most significant doubts about the creative
power of the mutation/selection mechanism has followed directly from the
elucidation of the nature of genetic information by molecular biologists in the
1950s and 60s. At first the discovery that the genetic information on DNA is
stored as a linear array of precisely sequenced nucleotide bases (the A’s, T’s,
G’s and C’s discussed above) helped to clarify the nature of many mutational
processes. Nevertheless, it also soon suggested limitations in the amount of
genetic novelty that random mutations could produce. Just as a sequence of
letters in an English text might be altered either by changing individual
letters one by one or combining and recombining whole sections of text, so too
did it occur to biologists that different lengths of genetic text might combine
and recombine in various ways at random. And, indeed, modern genetics has
established various mechanisms of mutational change—duplications, insertions,
inversions, recombinations, deletions and point mutations—that involve the
random alteration of the genetic text.
The difficulty for neo-Darwinism arises, not in
establishing the occurrence of such mutations, but in explaining how such
mutations could generate novel specified information. Imagine a computer
“mutating” at random the text of the play Hamlet by duplicating,
inverting, recombining and changing various sections. Would such a computer
simulation have a realistic chance of generating Stephen Hawking’s best-seller,
A Brief History of Time, even granting multiple millions of undirected
iterations? Beginning in the late 1960s, mathematicians and probability
theorists who began to analyze this problem found themselves deeply skeptical
about the efficacy of random mutation as a means of generating specified
information in the time available to the evolutionary process. See
Symposium, Mathematical Challenges to
the Neo-Darwinian Interpretation of Evolution (Paul S. Moorhead &
Martin M. Kaplan eds., 1967) (see especially papers and comments from M.
Eden, M. Shutzenberger, S. M. Ulam, and P. Gavaudan).
41See Behe, supra note 13 passim.
42See Bernard John & George L.Gabor Miklos, The
Eukaryote Genome in Development and Evolution passim (1988); A.H.
Brush, On the Origin of Feathers, 9 J.
Evolutionary Biology 131, 131–42 (1996); H. Allen Orr & Jerry A.
Coyne, The Genetics of Adaptation: A Reassessment, 140 Am. Naturalist 725, 725–42 (1992).
43See K.S.W.
Campbell & C.R. Marshall, Rates of Evolution, in Rates of Evolution 61, 66–100 (K.S.W.
Campbell & M.F. Day eds., 1987); George L. Gabor Miklos, Emergence of
Organizational Complexities During Metazoan Evolution: Perspectives from
Molecular Biology, Palaeontology and Neo-Darwinism, 15 Mem. Ass. Australas Palaeontols. 7,
7–41 (1993); Scott F. Gilbert et al., Resynthesizing Evolutionary and
Developmental Biology, 173 Developmental
Biology 357, 357–72 (1996).
44See James A.
Shapiro, Genome Organization, Natural Genetic Engineering and Adaptive
Mutation, 13 Trends in Genetics
98, 98–104 (1997); J.A. Shapiro, Natural Genetic Engineering in Evolution,
86 Genetica 99, 99–111 (1992);
Richard von Sternberg, Genome Self-Modification and Cellular Control of
Genome Reorganization, 89 Rivista di
Biologia/Biology Forum 423, 424–53 (1996).
45According to Stephen Jay Gould, “[t]he extreme rarity
of transitional forms in the fossil record persists as the trade secret of
paleontology. The evolutionary trees that adorn our textbooks have data only at
the tips and nodes of their branches; the rest is inference, however
reasonable, not the evidence of fossils.” Stephen Jay Gould, Evolution’s
Erratic Pace, Nat. Hist., May
1977, at 12, 14.
46The trilobite specialist Niles Eldredge, for instance,
of the American Museum in New York, and one of the authors of the hypothesis of
punctuated equilibria, describes commencing his work on the trilobite genus Phacops,
sampling Middle Devonian strata across the United States, only to discover to
his dismay that the trilobites were not varying smoothly and gradually between
species, as theory predicted. See Niles
Eldredge, Reinventing Darwin: The Great Debate at the High Table of
Evolutionary Theory passim (1995). Indeed, the fossil record as a whole proved so disturbing to
traditional Darwinism that Eldredge and Stephen Gould rejected the gradualist
neo-Darwinism model of evolutionary change in favor of a theory known as
“punctuated equilibrium.” According to punctuated equilibrium, the fossil
record shows long periods of stability “punctuated” by abrupt changes,
resulting in entirely new organisms. Punctuated equilibrium reduces the
conflict with the fossil record, but does so at the cost of abandoning a
sufficient explanatory mechanism for the appearance of biological novelty—the
very thing that made Darwin’s theory initially so attractive as a designer
substitute. See D. Raup, Conflicts Between Darwin and Paleontology,
50 Field Museum Nat. Hist. Bull.,
Jan. 1979, at 22, 22–29; Jeffrey H. Schwartz, Homeobox Genes, Fossils, and
the Origin of Species, 257 Anatomical
Rec. [New Anat.] 15,15–31 (1999).
47See A.D.
Bradshaw, Genostasis and the Limits to Evolution, 333 Series B Transactions Royal Soc’y London 289,
289–305 (1991); Brian K. Hall, Baupläne, Phylotypic Stages, and Constraint:
Why There Are So Few Types of Animals, 29 Evolutionary
Biology 215, 215–61 (1996); Kazuo Kawano, How Far Can the
Neo-Darwinism Be Extended? A Consideration from the History of Higher Taxa in
Coleoptera, 91 Rivista di Biologia /
Biology Forum 31, 31–52 (1998).
48See Gavin de Beer, Homology: An Unsolved Problem
passim (1971); Michael Denton,
Evolution: A Theory in Crisis 142–156 (1986).
49See John Gerhart & Marc Kirschner, Cells,
Embryos, and Evolution 125–46 (1997); John A. Davison, Semi-Meiosis
As an Evolutionary Mechanism, 111 J.
Theoretical Biology 725, 725–35 (1984); W.J. Dickinson, Molecules and
Morphology: Where’s the Homology?, 11 Trends
in Genetics 119, 119–21 (1995); Stephen J. Gaunt, Chick Limbs, Fly
Wings and Homology at the Fringe, 386 Nature
324, 324–25 (1997); Gregory A. Wray & Ehab Abouheif, When Is Homology
Not Homology?, 8 Current Opinion
Genetics & Dev. 675, 675–80 (1998).
50See Wallace Arthur, The Origin of Animal Body
Plans: A Study in Evolutionary Developmental Biology passim
(1997); Rudolf A. Raff, The Shape of Life passim (1996); César
Arenas-Mena et al., Expression of the Hox Gene Complex in the
Indirect Development of a Sea Urchin, 95 Proc.
Nat’l Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 13062, 13062–67 (1998); Barbara C. Boyer &
Jonathan Q. Henry, Evolutionary Modifications of the Spiralian Developmental
Program, 38 Am. Zoologist
621, 621–33 (1998); Graham E. Budd, Does Evolution in Body Patterning Genes
Drive Morphological Change—or Vice Versa?, 21 BioEssays 326, 326–32 (1999); Eric H. Davidson, How
Embryos Work: A Comparative View of Diverse Modes of Cell Fate Specification,
108 Development 365, 365–89
(1990); Gabriel Gellon & William McGinnis, Shaping Animal Body Plans in
Development and Evolution by Modulation of Hox Expression Patterns,
20 BioEssays 116, 116–25 (1998);
Miodrag Grbic et al., Development of Polyembryonic Insects: A Major
Departure from Typical Insect Embryogenesis, 208 Dev., Genes, & Evolution 69, 69–81 (1998).
51See Syozo Osawa, Evolution of the Genetic Code
passim (1995); T. Jukes & S. Osawa, Recent Evidence for Evolution
of the Genetic Code, in Evolution
of Life 79, 79–95 (S. Osawa & T. Honjo eds., 1991); Syozo Osawa et
al., Recent Evidence for Evolu-tion of the Genetic Code, 56 Microbiological Reviews 229, 229–64
(1992); Patrick J. Keeling & W. Ford Doolittle, A Non-Canonical Genetic
Code in an Early Diverging Eukaryotic Lineage, 15 EMBO J. 2285, 2285–90 (1996); Patrick J. Keeling & W.
Ford Doolittle, Widespread and Ancient Distribution of a Noncanonical
Genetic Code in Diplomonads, 14 Molecular
Biology & Evolution 895, 895–901 (1997); Anee Baroin Tourancheau et
al., Genetic Code Deviations in the Ciliates: Evidence for Multiple and
Independent Events, 14 EMBO J.
3262, 3262–67 (1995).
52Charles B. Thaxton et al., The
Mystery of Life’s Origin 42 (1984). In the
words of Jim Brooks, “the nitrogen content of early PreCambrian organic matter
is relatively low (less than .15%). From this we can be reasonably certain
that: there never was any substantial amount of ‘primitive soup’ on Earth when
ancient PreCambrian sediments were formed; if such a ‘soup’ ever existed it was
only for a brief period of time.” Jim
Brooks, Origins of Life 118 (1985) (emphasis omitted).
53After the 1960s a series of new fossil finds forced
scientists to revise progressively downward their estimates of the time
available for chemical evolution on earth. See J. Brooks & G. Shaw, Origin and Development of Living Systems
73, 267–305, 361 (1973); Brooks, supra
note 52, at 104–16; Thaxton,
et. al., supra note
52, at 69–72; Klaus Dose, The Origin of Life: More Questions Than Answers,
13 Interdisciplinary Sci. Reviews 348,
348–56 (1988); Richard E. Dickerson, Chemical Evolution and the
Origin of Life, Sci. Am.,
Sept. 1978, at 70–86 (1978); Andrew H. Knoll & Elso S. Barghoorn, Archean
Microfossils Showing Cell Division from the Swaziland System of South Africa,
198 Science 396, 396–98 (1977);
Donald R. Lowe, Stromatolites 3,400–Myr–Old from the Archean of
Western Australia, 284 Nature
441, 441–43 (1980); Kevin A. Maher & David J. Stevenson, Impact
Frustration of the Origin of Life, 331 Nature
612, 612–14 (1988); S.J. Mojzsis et al., Evidence for Life on Earth
Before 3,800 Million Years Ago, 384 Nature
55, 55–59 (1996); Leslie E. Orgel, The Origin of Life—A Review of Facts and
Speculations, 23 Trends Biochemical
Sci. 491, 491–95 (1998); H.D. Pflug & H. Jaeschke-Boyer, Combined
Structural and Chemical Analysis of 3,800–Myr-Old Microfossils, 280 Nature 483, 483–85 (1979); J. William
Schopf & Elso S. Barghoorn, Alga-Like Fossils from the Early Precambrian
of South Africa, 156 Science
508, 508–11 (1967); M.R.Walter et al., Stromatolites
3,400–3,500 Myr Old from the North Pole Area, Western Australia,
284 Nature 443, 443–45 (1980).
54See Robert Shapiro, Origins: A Skeptic’s Guide to
the Creation of Life on Earth passim (1986); Thaxton et al., supra note 52,
at 69–98; Joel S. Levine, The Photochemistry of the Paleoatmosphere, 18 J. Molecular Evolution 161, 161–72
(1982).
55Klaus Dose, Origin of
Life: More Questions than Answers 348–56
(1988); Shapiro, supra
note 54, at 98–116; Thaxton et al.,
supra note 52, at 99–112.
56Besides design, chemical evolutionary theorists have
relied on three general types of explanations for the origin of the specified
complexity (specified information) found in DNA: chance, prebiotic natural
selection, and self-organization. Numerous problems have been found with each
of these explanations:
(1) Chance-Based Models. See Emile Borel, Probabilities and Life 28
(Maurice Baudin trans. 1962) (1943); A.G.
Cairns-Smith, The Life Puzzle 95 (1971); Hubert P. Yockey, Information Theory and Molecular Biology passim
(1992); Michael J. Behe, Experimental Support for Regarding Functional
Classes of Proteins to Be Highly Isolated from Each Other, in Darwinism: Science or Philosophy 60,
60–71 (J. Buell & G. Hearn eds. 1994); Ilya Prigogine et al., Thermodynamics
of Evolution, Physics Today,
Nov. 1972, at 23, 23–28; John F. Reidhaar-Olson & Robert T. Sauer, Functionally
Acceptable Substitutions in Two Alpha-Helical Regions of Lambda Repressor, 7 Proteins: Structure, Function, &
Genetics 306, 306–16 (1990); Hubert P. Yockey, A Calculation of the
Probability of Spontaneous Biogenesis by Information Theory, 67 J. Theoretical Biology 377, 377–98
(especially 380) (1977).
(2) Pre-biotic Natural Selection: See Ludwig von
Bertalanffy, Robots, Men and Minds 82 (1967); Christian de Duve, Blueprint for a cell: The
Nature and Origin of Life 187 (1991); Dean H. Kenyon, Foreword to
Thaxton et al., supra note
52, at v–viii (1984); Peter T. Mora, The Folly of Probability, in
The Origins of Prebiological Systems and
of Their Molecular Matrices 39, 39–64 (Sidney W. Fox ed., 1965); Peter
T. Mora, Urge and Molecular Biology, 199 Nature 212, 212–19 (1963); H.H. Pattee, The Problem of
Biological Hierarchy, in 3 Towards
a Theoretical Biology 117, 117–36 (C.H. Waddington ed., 1970); Gerard
Schramm, Synthesis in Nucleosis and Polynucleotides with Metaphosphate
Esters, in The Origins of
Prebiological Systems and of Their Molecular Matrices 309, 309–15
(Sidney W. Fox ed. 1965).
(3) Self-Organization: See Percival Davis & Dean H. Kenyon, Of Pandas
and People: The Central Question of Biological Origins passim
(1993); Bernd-Olaf Küppers, Information
and the Origin of Life 170–72 (1990); Robert Shapiro, Origins 117–31 (1986); Hubert P. Yockey, Information Theory and
Molecular Biology 259–93 (1992); John Horgan, The World According to
RNA, Sci. Am., Jan. 1996, at
27, 27–30; Dean Kenyon & Gordon C.
Mills, The RNA World: A Critique, 17 Origins
& Design 9 passim (1996); Randall A. Kok et al., A
Statistical Examination of Self-Ordering of Amino Acids in Proteins, 18 Origins Life & Evolution Biosphere
135, 135–42 (1988); Stephen C. Meyer, DNA by Design: An Inference to the
Best Explanation for the Origin of Biological Information, 1 Rhetoric & Pub. Aff. 519, 519–56
(1998) [hereinafter Meyer, DNA By Design]; Stephen C. Meyer, The
Explanatory Power of Design, in Mere
Creation: Science, Faith and Intelligent Design 128–134 (William A.
Dembksi ed., 1998) [hereinafter Meyer, Explanatory Power]; Robert
Shapiro, Prebiotic Ribose Synthesis: A Critical Analysis, 18 Origins Life & Evolution Biosphere
71, 71–85 (1988); Charles B. Thaxton & Walter L. Bradley Information and
the Origin of Life, in The
Creation Hypothesis: Scientific Evidence for an Intelligent Designer
173, 173–210 (J.P. Moreland ed., 1994) [hereinafter Thaxton & Bradley, Information
and Origin].
57See Jaques Monod, Chance and Necessity 143
(1971); Robert Shapiro, Origins
132–54 (1986); K.R. Popper, Scientific
Reduction and the Essential Incompleteness of all Science, in Studies in the Philosophy of Biology
259, 259 (F.J. Ayala & T. Dobzhansky eds., 1974); Massimo Pigliucci, Where
Do We Come From? A Humbling Look at the Biology of Life’s Origin, Skeptical Inquirer, Sept.-Oct. 1999, at
21, 21–27.
58See Curtis & Barnes, Invitation to Biology
passim (5th ed. 1994); Douglas J.
Futuyma, Evolutionary Biology passim (3d ed. 1998); Guttman, Biology passim (1999); Starr & Taggart, Biology: The Unity and
Diversity of Life passim (8th ed. 1998); Mills et al., supra note
8, at 78–83; Jonathan Wells, Haeckel’s Embryos & Evolution: Setting the
Record Straight, 61 Am. Biology
Tchr. 345, 345–49 (1999); Jon-athan Wells, Second Thoughts About
Peppered Moths, Scientist,
May 24, 1999, at 13.
59See Mills et
al., supra note 8, at 78–83.
60See Antonio
Lazcano & Stanley L. Miller, The Origin and Early Evolution of Life:
Prebiotic Chemistry, the Pre-RNA World, and Time, 85 Cell 793, 793 (1996); Stanley L. Miller, The Prebiotoc
Synthesis of Organic Compounds As a Step Toward the Origin of Life, in
Major Events in the History of Life
5 (J. William Schopf ed., 1993).
61See, e.g.,
Thaxton & Bradley, Information and Origin, supra note 56, at
173–210.
62See Kenneth R. Miller & Joseph Levine, Biology
344 (4th ed. 1998); Alton L. Biggs et
al., Biology: The Dynamics of Life 227–28 (1991).
63See Eugenie C.
Scott, Keep Science Free from Creationism, Insight, Feb. 21, 1994, at 29, 29; U.S. Commission on
Civil Rights, Hearings, Seattle Washington, Aug. 21, 1998 <http://w1.548.telia.com/~454804688/civilright.html>.
64See William B.
Provine, Review of National
Academy of Sciences, Teaching About Evolution and The Nature of Science
<http://fp.bio.utk.edu/darwin/NAS
guidebook/provine_1.html>.
65Behe, supra note 13.
66Thaxton et al., supra note 52.
67Kenyon & Davis, supra note 56.
68Mere Creation: Science, Faith
& Intelligent Design (William A.
Dembski ed., 1998).
69Willam A. Dembski, The Design
Inference: Eliminating Change Through Small Probabilities (1998).
70Id.
71See id. passim.
72See id. at
1–35.
73Complex sequences are those that exhibit an irregular
and improbable arrangement that defies expression by a simple rule or
algorithm. A specification, on the other hand, is a match or correspondence
between a physical system or sequence and a set of independent functional
requirements or constraints. To illustrate these concepts (of complexity and
specification), consider the following three sets of symbols:
“inetehnsdysk]idfawqnz,mfdifhsnmcpew,ms.s/a”
“Time and tide
waits for no man.”
“ABABABABABABABABABABABABAB”
Both the first and second sequences shown above are
complex because both defy reduction to a simple rule. Each represents a highly
irregular, aperiodic and improbable sequence of symbols. The third sequence is
not complex, but is instead highly ordered and repetitive. Of the two complex
sequences, only one exemplifies a set of independent functional
requirements—i.e., is specified. English has a number of such functional
requirements. For example, to convey meaning in English one must employ
existing conventions of vocabulary (associations of symbol sequences with
particular objects, concepts or ideas) and existing conventions of syntax and
grammar (such as “every sentence requires a subject and a verb”). When
arrangements of symbols “match” or utilize existing vocabulary and grammatical
conventions (i.e., functional requirements), communication can occur. Such
arrangements exhibit “specification.” The second sequence (“Time and tide waits
for no man”) clearly exhibits such a match between itself and the preexisting
requirements of vocabulary and grammar. It has employed these conventions to
express a meaningful idea.
Indeed, of the three sequences above only the second
(“Time and tide waits for no man”) manifests both the jointly necessary
indicators of a designed system. The third sequence lacks complexity, though it
does exhibit a simple periodic pattern, a specification of sorts. The first sequence
is complex, but not specified as we have seen. Only the second sequence
exhibits both complexity and specification. Thus, according to Dembski’s
theory, only the second sequence, but not the first and third, implicates an
intelligent cause—as indeed our intuition tells us. See Dembski, supra note 69; Meyer, DNA
by Design, supra note 56; see also Stephen C. Meyer, DNA
and the Origin of Life: Information,
Specification and Explanation, in Darwinism,
Design and Public Education (John A. Campbell ed., forthcoming 2001),
also available in pre-publication form at www.discovery.org/viewDB. See also Stephen C. Meyer et al., The
Cambrian Explosion: Biology’s Big Bang,
in Darwinism, Design and Public
Education (John A. Campbell ed., forthcoming 2001), also available
through the Discovery Institute website.
74See Dembski, supra note 69, at
36–66.
75Id. at 36.
76See id. at
36–66.
77See id.
78See Review, Macromolecular
Machines, 92 Cell 291 (1998).
79See Bruce
Alberts, The Cell as a Collection of Protein Machines: Preparing the Next
Generation of Molecular Biologists, 92 Cell
291 (1998).
80Id. at 291.
81See id.
82See id.
83Behe, supra note 13, at 179.
84See id.
85See id. at
69–73.
86See id. at 3–164.
87See id. at
165–86.
88See id. at
179. See also Behe, infra
note 89.
89Since the publication of Behe’s book in 1996, some
critics, notably biologist Ken Miller, have argued that some recent (post-1996)
scientific articles do suggest plausible ways of assembling irreducibly complex
systems in a gradual Darwinian fashion. Behe has responded to these claims. He
has argued that (a) the papers that Miller cites often do not make the claims
that Miller uses them to make and (b) those Darwinian scenarios that Miller
(and others) do offer lack sufficient biochemical plausibility and specificity
to solve the problem of the origin of Darwin. For Behe’s responses to Miller, see
Michael J. Behe Answering Scientific Criticisms of Intelligent Design in
Science and Evidence of Design in the
Universe 121 (2000); see also Irreducible Complexity and the
Evolutionary Literature: Response to Critics, archived at
<http://www.crsc.org/fellows/
MichaelBehe/index.html>.
90See id. at 187–231.
91See id. at
187–208.
92Dean H. Kenyon & Gary
Steinman, Biochemical Predestination (1969).
93See id. at 36,
219–69.
94Richard Dawkins, River Out of
Eden 17 (1995).
95Bill Gates, The Road Ahead 228 (1996).
96See Sahotra
Sarkar, Biological Information: A Skeptical Look at Some Central Dogmas of
Molecular Biology, in The Philosophy
and History of Molecular Biology: New Perspectives 191 (Sahotra Sarkar
ed., 1996).
97See Meyer, DNA
by Design, supra note 56, 519–56; Meyer, Explanatory Power, supra
note 56, at 520.
98See Meyer et
al., supra note 73.
99See id.
100See id.
101See id.
102See id.
103See id.
104See Jonathan
Wells & Paul Nelson, Homology: A Concept in Crisis, Origins & Design, Fall 1997, at 12
(arguing that “naturalistic mechanisms proposed to explain homo-logy do not fit
the evidence”).
105See id.
106See Ayala, supra
note 7.
107See Miller & Levine, supra note
5.
108See John A.
Campbell, Intelligent Design, Darwinism, and the Philosophy of Public
Education, 1 Rhetoric and Public
Affairs 469, 481 (1998) (proposing that students will learn more about
Darwin’s theory by studying “intelligent design”).
109“Explanations employing nonnaturalistic or supernatural
events, whether or not explicit reference is made to a supernatural being, are
outside the realm of science and not part of a valid science curriculum.” National Academy of Science, supra
note 14, at 127.
110See McLean v.
Arkansas Bd. of Educ., 529 F. Supp. 1255, 1267 (E.D. Ark. 1982) (“[T]he
essential characteristics of science are: (1) It is guided by natural law; (2)
It has to be explanatory by reference to natural law; (3) It is testable
against the empirical world; (4) Its conclusions are tentative, i.e., are not
necessarily the final word; and (5) It is falsifiable.”).
111See infra Part
VI. E.
112See id.
113See id. at
1258, 1264. The court specifically found that the Arkansas law “was passed with
the specific purpose . . . of advancing religion.” Id.
at 1264. This placed the law directly in conflict with the First Amendment’s
establishment clause under the Lemon test. See id. For a statute
to pass constitutional muster under Lemon it must have a secular
legislative purpose, it cannot either advance or inhibit religion, and it must
not foster an excessive entanglement between government and religion. See
Lemon v. Kurtzman, 403 U.S. 602, 612–13 (1971); Stone v. Graham, 449 U.S. 39,
40 (1980). A violation of any of the prongs of the Lemon test results in
a violation of the Establishment Clause. See McLean, 529 F. Supp.
at 1258. The court in McLean found that the Arkansas law’s purpose was
to advance religion in the public schools in violation of Lemon's first
prong. See id. at 1264. The court also found that the Arkansas law would
result in an impermissible entanglement with religion, violating the third
prong of Lemon. See id. at 1272.
114See McLean,
529 F. Supp. at 1267–72. The court’s language was unambiguous: “Section 4(a)
[of the Arkansas Act] lacks legitimate educational value because ‘creation
science’ as defined in that section is simply not science.” Id. See
generally Robert M. Gordon, Note, McLean v. Arkansas Board of Education:
Finding the Science in “Creation Science,” 77 Nw. U. L. Rev. 374 passim (1982) (discussing court’s
finding that creation science is unscientific).
115See McLean,
529 F. Supp. at 1272.
116See id. at
1267.
117See id.
118See id. In the
court’s words, these five points are the “essential characteristics of
science.” Id. at 1267.
119See id.
120See id.
121See id.
122See id.
123482 U.S. 578 (1987). See discussion infra
Part VI.D.
124See National Academy of Science, supra
note 14 passim.
125See Larry
Laudan, Science at the Bar—Causes for Concern, in But Is It Science? 351, 355 (Michael
Ruse ed., 1988) [hereinafter Laudan, Science] (“It simply will not do
for the defenders of science to invoke philosophy of science when it suits
them . . . and to dismiss it as ‘arcane’ and ‘remote’ when
it does not.”); Philip Quinn, The Philosopher of Science as Expert Witness,
in But Is It Science? 367,
384 (Michael Ruse ed., 1988) (crit-icizing expert testimony in McClean
as “fallacious” and not representative of “settled consensus of opinion in the
relevant community of scholars”).
126Laudan, Science, supra note 125, at 355.
127See id.;
Quinn, supra note 125, at 367–85.
128See Laudan, Science,
supra note 125, at 354–55.
129See id. at
353–54.
130McLean v. Arkansas Bd. of Educ., 529 F. Supp. 1255
(E.D. Ark. 1982). See dis-cussion infra Part VI.D.
131See Imre
Lakatos, Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes,
in Scientific Knowledge: Basic
Issues in the Philosophy of Science 173 (Janet A. Kouvray ed., 1987)
(presenting scientific progress as rational process rather than religious
conversions).
132See id.
133See id. at
175.
134See id. at
192.
135See Lakatos, supra
note 133, at 175.
136See id. passim.
137Larry Laudan, The Demise of the Demarcation Problem,
in But Is It Science? 337,
349 (Michael Ruse ed., 1988).
138John Buell, Broaden Science Curriculum, Dallas Morning News, March 10, 1989, at
A21 (quoting unidentified “authority”).
139See Laudan, Science,
supra note 125, at 354.
140See id. at
352.
141Id.
142Id.
143Id.
144See id. at
352–53.
145See Charles Darwin, On The Origin of Species by Means
of Natural Selection 411–34 (photo. reprint, Harvard Univ. Press 1964)
(1859).
146See id.
147Laudan, Science, supra note 125, at 354.
148Id.
149Id.
150See id.
151See, e.g.,
Stephen C. Meyer, The Demarcation of Science and Religion, in The History of Science and Religion in the
Western Tradition: An Encyclopedia 17, 22 (Gary Ferngren et al., eds.,
2000) (“[I]nsofar as both creationist and evolutionary theories constitute historical
theories about past causal events, neither explains exclusively by reference to
natural law.”); Stephen C. Meyer, The Nature of Historical Science and the
Demarcation of Design and Descent, in 4 Facets of Faith and Science 91 (Jitse M. van der Meer ed.,
1996) [hereinafter Meyer, Demarcation]; Stephen C. Meyer, The
Methodological Equivalence of Design & Descent: Can There Be a Scientific
“Theory of Creation?”, in The Creation Hypothesis: Scientific Evidence
for an Intelligent Designer 67, 102 (J.P. Moreland ed., 1994)
[hereinafter Meyer, Equivalence] (“The exclusion of one of the logically
possible programs of origins research by
assumption . . . seriously diminishes the significance of
any claim to theoretical superiority by advocates of a remaining group.”).
152See Laudan, Science, supra note 125, at 354.
153See Elliott Sober, Philosophy of Biology
27, 56 (1993) (finding that creat-ionism and Darwinism both use characteristic
approaches and techniques to attempt to explain certain phenomena).
154See Meyer, Demarcation,
supra note 151, at 91-130; Meyer, Equivalence, supra note
153, at 99 (“[T]he conjunction of the methodological equivalence of design and
descent and the existence of a convention that regards descent as scientific
implies that design should—by that same convention—be regarded as scientific
too.”).
155Interestingly, there is considerable evidence that some
advocates of these demarcation arguments in the Arkansas trial knew them to be
inadequate at the time of the trial itself. For example, Barry Gross, a
philosopher of science who served as a consultant to the law firm of Skadden,
Arps (who represented the ACLU), has written that he informed the ACLU at the
time of the trial that the McLean criteria were inaccurate and
inadequate. Barry R. Gross, Commentary: Philosophers at the Bar—Some Reasons
for Restraint, Science, Technology
and Human Values, Fall 1983, at 36. As he wrote after the trial,
“Philosophically, these criteria may have been acceptable sixty or eighty years
ago, but they are not rigorous, they are redundant, and they take no account of
many distinctions nor of historical cases. The opinion does not state whether
they are singly necessary or jointly sufficient. One would not recommend to
graduate school a student who could do no better than this.” Id.
156See Hearings,
supra note 63.
157See U.S. Comm’n on Civil Rights, supra note 63.
158Speech by Michael Ruse to the Annual Meeting of the
American Assoc. for the Advancement of Science (Feb. 13, 1993) (visited Feb.
17, 2000) <http://www.leaderv-.com/orgs/am/orpages/or151/mr93tran.html>.
159Michael Ruse, Monad to Man 511–17 (1996).
160See Laudan, Science,
supra note 125, at 351–55.
161See Hearings,
supra note 63.
162See id.
163See id.
164509 U.S. 579 (1993).
165Id. at 579.
166293 F. 1013, 1014 (D.C. Cir. 1923) (holding that “while
courts will go a long way in admitting expert testimony deduced from a
well-recognized scientific principle or discovery, the thing from which the
deduction is made must be sufficiently established to have gained general
acceptance in the particular field in which it belongs”).
167See id. at
1013–14.
168See id. at
1014.
169See id.
170See Daubert,
509 U.S. at 585 (“In the 70 years since its formulation in the Frye
case, the ‘general acceptance’ test has been the dominant standard for
determining the admissibility of novel scientific evidence at trial.”) (citing Eric D. Green & Charles R. Nesson,
Problems, Cases, and Materials on Evidence 649 (1983)).
171See Daubert,
509 U.S. at 585–86. One criticism was the court’s reliance on pro-fessional
acceptance by the scientific community as a gauge of legitimate science. A
popular evidence casebook summarizes one of the arguments against the Frye
ruling: “[T]he extent of the acceptance of the technique by peers is not the
substantive test of scientific validity; the degree of acceptance is merely
circumstantial evidence that the hypothesis has been properly validated by
experimentation.” Ronald L. Carlson et
al., Evidence in the Nineties 289 (3d ed. 1991) (citing Bert Black, A
Unified Theory of Scientific Evidence, 56 Fordham
L. Rev. 595, 625, 632 (1988)).
172See State v.
York, 564 A.2d 389 (Me. 1989). In ruling on the admissibility of a social
worker’s testimony regarding the behavior of an eight-year old child, the Maine
court found that the guiding principle in evaluating the legitimacy of
scientific evidence is “solid empirical research.” Id. at 390.
173Id. at 390.
174Id. at 390–91.
175509 U.S. 579 (1993).
176See id. at
582.
177See id. at
587–89.
178Id. at 590.
179Id.
180Daubert’s view
of science was recently strengthened by the Supreme Court's ruling in Kumho
Tire Co. v. Carmichael, 526 U.S. 137 (1999). Kumho extended Daubert
to apply to the expert testimony of nonscientists offered under Rule 702. See
id. at 141. The Court expanded the number of criteria which could be
considered when evaluating evidence under Daubert, but continued to
apply its fundamental rule, that scientific reliability should be considered a
function of the coherence of the methodology employed, not by whether a view
commands majority status in the particular discipline. See id. at 149
(holding that trial judge’s duty is to “determine whether the testimony [in
question] has ‘a reliable basis in the knowledge and experience of [the
relevant] discipline’” (quoting Daubert, 509 U.S. at 592 (second
alteration in original)).
181See, e.g.,
Commonwealth v. Lanigan, 641 N.E.2d 1342, 1349 (Mass. 1994) (adopting Daubert
test); Hand v. Norfolk S. Ry. Co., No. 03A01-9704-CV-00123, 1998 WL 281946, at
*4 (Tenn. App. 1998) (following, but not officially adopting, Daubert
test); State v. Streich, 658 A.2d 38, 47 (Vt. 1995) (applying Daubert’s
factors); State v. Anderson, 881 P.2d 29, 36 (N.M. 1994) (citing Daubert
to support judicially created admissibility considerations). But see
State v. Tankersley, 956 P.2d 486, 491 (Ariz. 1998) (refusing to replace Frye
with Daubert, but noting that issue not properly before court); State v.
Copeland, 922 P.2d 1304, 1310 (Wash. 1996) (holding Frye, not Daubert,
test applied to admission of scientific evidence).
182See Daubert,
509 U.S. at 594 (“The inquiry envisioned by Rule 702 is, we emphasize, a flexible
one.”).
183See id. at
590; State v. York, 564 A.2d 389, 390–91 (Me. 1989).
184See Daubert,
590 U.S. at 590.
185See, e.g.,
United States v. Chischilly, 30 F.3d 1144, 1154 (9th Cir. 1994) (holding that
judges should not supplant jury’s function of evaluating evidence by
‘“crossexam-ination, presentation of contrary evidence, and careful
instruction’” of juries) (quoting Daubert, 509 U.S. at 596)).
186A good example of a minority viewpoint that is worthy
of scientific debate is Francis Crick's theory that life originated on a
distant planet and was “seeded” by a more developed civilization that
transported life via unmanned spacecraft. See generally Francis H. Crick
& Leslie E. Orgel, Directed Panspermia, 19 Icarus 341, 341 (1973) (explaining Francis Crick’s “theory
that organisms were deliberately transmitted to the earth by intelligent beings
on another planet”). As one commentator stated, this theory “remains outside
the mainstream of science; however, the mental exercises that Crick entertains
both for and against his theory are stimulating and informative.” A Visit
With Dr. Francis Crick, Access
Excellence Classic Collection, visited Feb. 15, 2000
<http://www.accessexcellence.org/
AE/AEC/CC/crick.html>
187See supra Part
II.B.
188See Davis & Kenyon, supra note
56.
189See Jay D.
Wexler, Note, Of Pandas, People, and the First Amendment: The
Constitutionality of Teaching Intelligent Design in the Public Schools, 49 Stan. L. Rev. 439, 467–68 (1997).
190See id. The
First Amendment's establishment clause reads “Congress shall make no law
respecting an establishment of religion . . . .” U.S. Const. amend. I. The Establishment
Clause has been incorporated by the Fourteenth Amendment, so its prohibition
against the establishment of religion applies equally to the state and federal
governments. See Everson v. Board of Educ., 330 U.S. 1, 15–16 (1947).
191See Wexler, supra
note 189, at 468.
192Indeed, to Wexler, the scientific merit of intelligent
design is “not . . . a very important question after all.”
Wexler, supra note 189, at 468. Instead, the only critical question is
whether the teaching of intelligent design violates the requirement that
schools refrain from teaching religion. See id. Since intelligent design
implies the existence of a designer, it is logical to assume “a supreme,
supernatural being who designed, coordinated, and created all of nature
according to a master plan.” Id. at 460. For this reason, any attempt to
teach intelligent design is inherently religious and therefore must be excluded
from the public school system. See id. at 462–63.
193Id. at 468.
194See id.
195482 U.S. 578 (1987).
196See Lemon v.
Kurtzman, 403 U.S. 602, 612–13 (1971).
197See, e.g.,
Texas Monthly, Inc. v. Bullock, 489 U.S. 1, 25 (1989) (striking down tax
exemption for religious periodical as non-neutral benefit).
198See Witters v.
Washington Dep’t of Servs. for the Blind, 474 U.S. 481, 489 (1986) (holding
that state aid to blind student studying theology was not barred by First
Amendment).
199See, e.g.,
United States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163, 164–65 (1965) (seeking exemption from
military service obligation for conscientious objections based on religious
belief); Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.S. 398, 399–402 (1963) (seeking exemption
based on religious belief from requirement to work on Saturday to receive
unemployment benefits); Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205, 207 (1972) (seeking
religious exemption from compulsory school attendance statute); Thomas v.
Review Bd. of Ind. Employment Security Div., 450 U.S. 707, 709–13 (1981)
(seeking religious exemption from requirement to work in armament factory to
receive unemployment benefits).
200See, e.g.,
Texas Monthly, Inc., 489 U.S. at 25 (challenging tax exemption for reli-gious
periodicals).
201See Seeger,
380 U.S. at 176. Nevertheless, courts have rejected claims of religious
motivation where they find that religious language merely affects a form of
fraud. See, e.g., United States v. Meyers, 95 F.3d 1475, 1481 (10th Cir.
1996) (rejecting defendant’s claim that he was wrongfully convicted of
violating drug laws, in contravention of his right to free exercise of
religion, because of his membership in Church of Marijuana).
202See, e.g.,
Grove v. Mead Sch. Dist. No. 354, 753 F.2d 1528, 1534 (9th Cir. 1985) (finding
that use of literature text offensive to fundamentalist Christians did not
result in promotion of alleged religion of secular humanism); Brown v. Woodland
Joint Unified Sch. Dist., 27 F.3d 1373, 1378–83 (9th Cir. 1994) (reasoning that
teaching students about witchcraft and inviting them to participate in
classroom poetry and chanting did not promote “religion” of witchcraft).
203See Malnak v.
Yogi, 592 F.2d 197, 198–99 (3d Cir. 1979). We may use the term “religious” in a
metaphorical sense, such as commenting that a person is “religious” about
getting exercise or watching a favorite sporting event. But it requires more
than a great deal of passion or commitment to an activity or idea to make
something religious for legal purposes. See Meyers, 95 F.3d at
1481–84.
204The only successful claim has been Malnak, 592
F.2d at 198–99 (enjoining practitioners from teaching “Science of Creative
Intelligence-Transcendental Meditation” to public school students because
practices were too closely related to traditional Hindu doctrines). The more
common result is to deny the claim that the defendant’s belief system operates
in a way analogous to religion. See, e.g., Grove, 753 F.2d at
1537–38; Brown, 27 F.3d at 1380–81.
205See Dmitry N.
Feofanov, Defining Religion: An Immodest Proposal, 23 Hofstra L. Rev. 309, 313 (1994)
(stating that “we need a definition of religion because it determines what is
protected and what is not”); see also Steven D. Collier, Comment, Beyond
Seeger/Welsh: Redefining Religion Under the Constitution, 31 Emory L.J. 973, 975 n.14 (1982) (“A
clear definition of religion is essential to any case based solely on the
religion clauses, since the First Amendment claim disappears if ‘religion’ is
not involved.” (footnote omitted) (citing Theriault v. Silber, 453 F. Supp. 254
(W.D. Tex. 1978), appeal dismissed 579 F.2d 302 (5th Cir. 1978), and
cert. denied, 440 U.S. 917 (1979); United States v. Kuch, 288 F. Supp. 439
(D.D.C. 1968); Yoder, 406 U.S. at 215)).
206See Alvarado
v. City of San Jose, 94 F.3d 1223, 1227 (9th Cir. 1996). The court described
the attempt to define religion both as a general term and for Establishment
Clause purposes as a “notoriously difficult, if not impossible, task.” Id.
(citing James M. Donovan, God is as God Does: Law, Anthropology, and the
Definition of “Religion,” 6 Seton
Hall Const. L.J. 23 (1995); Africa v. Pennsylvania, 662 F.2d 1025, 1031
(3d Cir. 1981), cert. denied, 456 U.S. 908 (1982)).
207See Peloza v.
Capistrano Unified Sch. Dist., 37 F.3d 517, 521 (9th Cir. 1994).
208See Smith v.
Board of Sch. Comm’rs, 827 F.2d 684, 690–95 (11th Cir. 1987).
209See United States
v. Allen, 760 F.2d 447, 450 (2d Cir. 1985).
210133 F.2d 703 (2d Cir. 1943).
211Id. at 708.
212Different religions have different understandings of
the nature of religion and religious belief. Protestant theologian, Paul
Tillich, defined religion as being an “ultimate concern.” Paul Tillich, The Shaking of the Foundations
57 (1948). This definition would expand religion beyond traditional theistic
grounds to include any strongly held ideological belief concerning the ultimate
meaning and purpose of the universe. The Letter of James in the New Testament
states that “[r]eligion that is pure and undefiled before God, the Father, is
this: to care for orphans and widows in their distress, and to keep oneself
unstained by the world.” James 1:27 (New Revised Standard Version). The
Catechism of the Catholic Church identifies true religion with the teachings of
the Catholic and apostolic Church. See Catechism
of the Catholic Church ¶ 870. Some evangelical Protestant theologians
have even argued that Christianity itself is not properly thought of as a
religion. See Dietrich
Bonhoeffer, The Cost of Discipleship passim (rev. ed. 1967); Karl Barth, The Epistle to the Romans
(Edwin C. Hoskyns trans., Oxford Univ. Press 1933) (6th ed. 1928). Even the
role of God in religion is disputed. Some religious traditions (Christianity,
Judaism, Islam) affirm monotheism, some (Hinduism, Jainism, animism) affirm a
belief in a multiplicity of deities, and others (Buddhism, Confucianism,
Taoism) hold no particular view of God or the gods at all. See Willard E. Arnett, A Modern Reader in the
Philosophy of Religion 4–5 (1966).
213See Val D.
Ricks, To God God’s, To Caesar Caesar’s, and To Both the Defining of
Religion, 26 Creighton L. Rev.
1053, 1054–55 (1993). According to Ricks, “only a few United States Supreme
Court cases have mentioned the issue, and none have addressed it directly.” Id.
at 1054 n.2 (citing Thomas v. Review Bd., 450 U.S. 707 (1981); Wisconsin v.
Yoder, 406 U.S. 205 (1972); Welsh v. United States, 398 U.S. 333 (1970); United
States v. Seeger, 380 U.S. 163 (1965); Torcaso v. Watkins, 367 U.S. 488 (1961);
United States v. Ballard, 322 U.S. 78 (1944); Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 333
(1890); Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145 (1878)). Ricks also cites to the
relatively small number of appellate court decisions attempting to define
religion. See id. (citing Africa v. Pennsylvania, 662 F.2d 1025 (3d Cir.
1981), cert. denied, 456 U.S. 908 (1982); Malnak v. Yogi, 592 F.2d 197
(3d Cir. 1979) (Adams, J., concurring); International Soc’y for Krishna
Consciousness, Inc. v. Barber, 650 F.2d 430 (2d Cir. 1981); Founding Church of
Scientology v. United States, 409 F.2d 1146 (D.C. Cir.), cert. denied,
396 U.S. 963 (1969); United States v. Kauten, 133 F.2d 703 (2d Cir. 1943)).
214See generally
David K. DeWolf, State Action Under the Religion Clauses: Neutral in Result
or Neutral in Treatment?, 24 U.
Rich. L. Rev. 253, 271–75 (1990) (“[T]he Court’s opinion [in Seeger]
should be read as demonstrating the Court’s recognition that when legal rights
are made dependent upon theological categories, a court cannot make a legal
determination without at the same time becoming entangled in the most sensitive
of theological issues.”).
21537 F.3d 517 (9th Cir. 1994).
216Id. at 519–21.
217Id. at 521.
218Id. (footnote
and citation omitted) (citing Smith v. Board of Sch. Comm’rs, 827 F.2d 684,
690–95 (11th Cir. 1987); United States v. Allen, 760 F.2d 447, 450–51 (2d Cir.
1985)).
219Id. at 521 n.5
(citing Allen, 760 F.2d at 450–51 (quoting Laurence H. Tribe, American Constitutional Law 827–28
(1978))). Tribe argues that the balance between the Free Exercise and
Establishment Clauses of the First Amendment should be struck by favoring
religious liberty, rather than by sacrificing religious liberty to the
Establishment Clause. See Tribe,
supra, at 827–28.
22094 F.3d 1223 (9th Cir. 1996).
221See id. at
1226.
222See id. at
1228–31.
223See id. at
1229. This test was first proposed in Malnak v. Yogi, 592 F.2d 197,
207–10 (3d Cir. 1979) (Adams, J., concurring). The Third Circuit adopted the
test in Africa v. Pennsylvania, 662 F.2d 1025, 1032 (3d Cir. 1981).
224Alvarado, 94
F.3d at 1129 (quoting Africa, 662 F.2d at 1032).
225Id. (quoting Africa,
662 F.2d at 1035-36 (internal quotations omitted)).
22637 F.3d 517 (9th Cir. 1994).
22794 F.3d 1223 (9th Cir. 1996).
228See Peloza,
37 F.3d at 520; Alvarado, 94 F.3d at 1229.
229Alvarado, 94
F.3d at 1229 (quoting Africa v. Pennsylvania, 662 F.2d 1025, 1032 (3d Cir.
1981). Clearly the debate between Darwinists and design theorists about the
origin of apparent design could be characterized as a “fundamental” scientific
and philosophical issue. Nevertheless, neither Darwinism nor design theory
seeks to answer “ultimate” metaphysical questions, even though both theories
have implications for how such questions are approached. See infra notes
246–60 and accompanying text.
230See William A.
Dembski, Intelligent Design is Not Optimal Design (Jan. 2, 2000)
<http:\\www.discovery.org/crsc/CRSCdbEngine.php3?id=86>.
231See Stephen C.
Meyer, Return of the God Hypothesis, 9 J.
Interdisc. Stud. 1 passim (1999).
232482 U.S. 578 (1987).
233Edwards v. Aguillard, 482 U.S. 578, 605 (1986) (Powell,
J., concurring) (quoting McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.S. 420, 442 (1961)).
234Id. (Powell,
J., concurring).
235Alvarado, 94
F.3d at 1229 (quoting Africa, 662 F.2d at 1032).
236See supra
notes 63–75 and accompanying text.
237See id.
238See id.
239Id. (quoting Africa,
662 F.2d at 1032).
240See id.
241See, e.g.,
Center for the Renewal of Science & Culture, The Discovery Institute
(visited Apr. 21, 2000) <http:\\www.discovery.org/crsc> (proposing
alternatives to material-ism); The Michael Polanyi Center (visited Apr. 21,
2000) <<http://www.Baylor.edu~pol-anyi> (covering design-theoretic
concepts).
242See Behe, supra note 13, at 203.
243See Meyer, DNA
By Design, supra note 56.
244See supra
notes 30–32 and accompanying text.
245See Douglas J. Futuyma, Evolutionary Biology
5 (3d ed. 1998).
246See William
Provine, Evolution and the Foundation of Ethics, 3 MBL Science 25, 26 (1988) (“The implications
of modern evolutionary biology are
inescap-able . . . . [E]volutionary biology undermines
the fundamental assumptions underlying ethical systems in almost all cultures,
Western civilization in particular.”).
247See Stephen Jay Gould, Ever Since Darwin
147 (1977).
248Id.
249Id. at 267.
250Stephen Jay Gould, Wonderful
Life 323 (1989).
251One example is the debate over the most effective polio
vaccine—the one developed by Jonas Salk or the one developed by Albert Sabin.
The debate over superiority was not only about science, but involved
controversies over the rights of individual patients versus public health and
the proper role of doctors in public policy debates. See generally Reyes
v. Wyeth Lab., 498 F.2d 1264, 1294–95 (5th Cir. 1974) (holding that marketers
of oral polio vaccine may be liable when they failed to warn parents that
treatment was necessary); Theodore H. Davis, Jr. & Catherine B. Bowman, No-Fault
Compensation for Unavoidable Injuries: Evaluating the National Childhood
Vaccine Injury Compensation Program, 16 U.
Dayton L. Rev. 277, 281–85 (1991) (examining the efficacy of the
National Childhood Vaccine Injury Compensation program to compensate victims of
mandatory childhood vaccine programs while protecting vaccine manufacturers
from liability). Other examples could be easily multiplied, such as the issues
of global warming, the effect of electromagnetic radiation on health, and the
risks associated with cellular telephones or breast implants.
252See Ayala, supra
note 7, at 4–5.
253See Kenyon & Steinman, supra
note 95, at 6.
254See Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker 5
(1996).
255See id. at
1–6.
256George Gaylord Simpson, The
Meaning of Evolution 344 (rev. ed. 1967)
(emphasis added).
257Kenneth R. Miller & Joseph
Levine, Biology 658 (4th ed. 1998).
258Douglas J. Futuyma,
Evolutionary Biology 5 (3d ed. 1997).
259Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U.S. 97, 113 (1968) (Black,
J., concurring).
260See id. at
109–14 (Black, J., concurring).
261See Edwards v.
Aguillard, 482 U.S. 578, 605 (1987) (Powell, J., concurring) (arguing that
subject matter taught in school does not violate Establishment Clause simply
“because the material to be taught ‘happens to coincide or harmonize with the
tenets of some or all religions.’”) (quoting McGowan v. Maryland, 366 U.S. 420,
442 (1961)). The language from McGowan has been cited with approval in
numerous subsequent Supreme Court decisions. See Hernandez v.
Commissioner, 490 U.S. 680, 696 (1989); Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 682
(1984); Bob Jones Univ. v. United States, 461 U.S. 574, 604 n.30 (1983); Harris
v. McRae, 448 U.S. 297, 319 (1980); School Dist. v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203, 303
(1963) (Brennan, J., concurring).
262482 U.S. 579 (1987).
263See Wexler, supra
note 189, at 455–66.
264La. Rev. Stat. Ann. §§ 17:286.1–7 (West 1982).
265See id. §§
17286.3-4.
266See Edwards,
482 U.S. at 581.
267See id. at
581–582.
268See id. at
581.
269See id. at
582.
270See id.
271See id. at
582–94.
272403 U.S. 602 (1971). Although the Lemon test has
received scholarly criticism and has been qualified by the Court, see Lynch v.
Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 679 (1984), the Court continues to rely on the test’s
general framework. See Robert A. Sedler, Understanding the
Establishment Clause: The Perspective of Constitutional Litigation, 43 Wayne L. Rev. 1317, 1323 (1997). Two
exceptions are Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U.S. 783 (1983) and Rosenberger v.
Rector and Visitors of the University of Virginia, 515 U.S. 819
(1995). Neither of these cases, however, deals with the teachings of origins in
public schools.
273Lemon, 403
U.S. at 612–613.
274See Edwards,
482 U.S. at 583.
275Id. at 585
(quoting Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 690 (1984) (O’Connor, J.,
concurring)).
276See id. at
591–93. Because the Act violated the first prong, the Court did not address
whether the Act also violated the second or third prongs. See id..
277See id.
278See id. at
587.
279Id.
(alteration in original).
280See id. at
587–89.
281Id. at 587.
282See id.
283See id.
284See id. at
588.
285See id. at
588–89.
286See id. at
594.
287See id. at
593.
288Id. at 594.
289See id. at
593.
290See The National Academy of Sciences, Science and
Creationism: A View from the National Academy of Sciences 7 (2d ed.
1999); Scott, Testimony before U.S. Commission on Civil Rights, supra
note 63 (“I see [intelligent design theory] as a synonym for creation science.”).
291See Wexler, supra
note 189.
292482 U.S. 579 (1987).
293See id. at
596.
294See id. at
603–04; see also McLean v. Arkansas Bd. of Educ., 529 F. Supp. 1255, 1264–1265
(E.D. Ark. 1982) (“The evidence establishes that the definition of ‘creation
science’ . . . has as its unmentioned reference the first
11 chapters of the Book of Genesis. Among the many creation epics in human
history, the account of sudden creation from nothing, or creatio ex nihilo,
and subsequent destruction of the world by flood is unique to Genesis.”).
295See Numbers, The
Creationists, x.
296See Edwards,
482 U.S. at 594 (1987) (noting that “a variety
of . . . theor-ies . . . might be
validly [taught] with the clear secular intent of
enhancing . . . instruction. But because the primary
purpose of the . . . Act is to endorse a particular
religious doctrine,” it advances religion in violation of Establishment
Clause).
297See id.
Indeed, the Court recognized that some of these individual tenets may form
legitimate topics for scientific discussion, and thus could be included in a
valid public school science curriculum. For example, in reference to tenet (3),
scientists have increas-ingly debated whether or not there are limits to
morphological change among biological organisms. See supra note 47.
According to the neo-Darwinian synthesis there are no limits whatsoever: all
organisms trace their ancestry back to an original single-celled organism. Id.
This view is called “monophyly” or “common descent” and contrasts with
“polyphyly,” the view that some groups of organisms have separate ancestries.
Some scientists now cite evidence from the fossil record, molecular sequence
analyses, and developmental biology to support this latter view. Stuart A. Kauffman, The Origins of Order
(1993); Paul A. Nelson, On Common
Descent (forthcoming 2000); Malcolm S. Gordon, The Concept of
Monophyly: A Speculative Essay, 14 Biology
& Philosophy 331, 331–48 (1999); Christ-ian Schwabe, Theoretical
Limitations of Molecular Phylogenetics and the Evolution of Relaxins, 107B Comp. Biochemistry & Physiology
167, 167–77 (1994); G. Webster & Brian Goodwin, The Origin of Species: A
Structuralist Approach, 5 J. Soc.
& Biological Structures 15, 15–47 (1982); Carl Woese, The
Universal Ancestor, 95 Proc. Nat. Acad. Ser. USA 6854, 6854–59 (1998).
Similarly, many scientists have expressed increasing skepticism about the
sufficiency of the neo-Darwinian mechanisms of mutation and natural selection. Bernard John & George L. Gabor Miklos, The
Eukaryote Genome in Development and Evolution (1988); Rudolf A. Raff, The Shape of Life
(1996); G.L.G. Miklos & K.S.W. Campbell, From Protein Domains to Extinct
Phyla: Reverse-Engineering Approaches to the Evolution of Biological
Complexities, in Early Life
on Earth, Nobel Symposium No. 84, 501–16 (Stefan Bengtson ed. 1993).
Many science teachers will want to discuss these
scientific developments with their students.
298See Dembski, supra note 69, at 1–35.
299See Behe, supra note 13, at 39–45.
300See Hubert P. Yockey, Information Theory and
Molecular Biology 334 (1992); Werner
R. Loewenstein, The Touchstone of Life 15 (1999); Meyer, DNA by
Design, supra note 56, at 519–56; Meyer, Explanatory Power, supra
note 56, at 113–47; Thaxton et al.,
supra note 52, at 127–65, 188–215.
301See supra note
56 (discussing three explanations of origins of specified complexity).
302See Meyer, DNA
by Design, supra note 56, at 519–56; Meyer, Explanatory Power,
supra note 56, at 113–47; Behe, supra
note 13, at 252; Thaxton & Bradley, supra note 56, at 173–210.
303See Stephen C.
Meyer, The Return of the God Hypothesis, 11 J. Interdisc. Stud. 1, 1–38 (1999).
304See Phillip E.
Johnson, Darwinism and Theism, in Darwinism: Science or Philosophy 42,
42–50 (J. Buell & G. Hearn eds., 1994).
305See Brendan
Sweetman, Darwin vs. “Intelligent Design” Three Views on the Kansas
Controversy Over Teaching Evolution in Public Schools: What Evolution Tries to
Explain, And What It Leaves Unanswered, The
Kansas City Star, Aug. 22, 1999, at L1.
306See Lemon,
403 U.S. at 612.
307See Edwards,
482 U.S. at 581–82.
308See id. at
587.
309See id. at
589.
310See Lemon,
403 U.S. at 612.
311515 U.S. 819 (1995) (plurality opinion).
312See id. at
845–46.
313See id. at
829.
314See id. at
845–46; see also infra Part VII.A. (discussing Rosenberger
decision).
315Some would no doubt argue that there is no comparable
constitutional protection for religious viewpoints in the public high school
environment. On the contrary, the Court has extended the principle of viewpoint
neutrality to cover religious speech in the public high schools. See
Westside Community Bd. of Educ. v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226, 249 (1990) (holding
Equal Access Act, which requires student religious clubs to receive same
treatment as secular clubs, meets first prong of Lemon test: “Congress’
avowed purpose—to prevent discrimination against religious and other types of
speech—is undeniably secular”).
316See Doe v.
County of Montgomery, Ill., 915 F. Supp. 32, 35 (C.D. Ill. 1996) (stating that
“[b]efore the Court analyzes the [offending practice] under the Lemon
test, however, the Court first must determine whether there is even an issue of
religion”); Fleischfresser v. Directors of Sch. Dist. 200, 15 F.3d 680, 687
(7th Cir. 1994).
317See Edwards, 482 U.S. at 591–94.
318See id. at
590–91 (1987).
319See West
Virginia Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624, 642 (1943) (“If there is any
fixed star in our constitutional constellation, it is that no official, high or
petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion,
or other matters of opinion or force citizens to confess by word or act their
faith therein.”).
320Of course, it would still be objectionable to present a
religious theory as such. Although critics of teaching alternatives to Darwin
frequently suggest that teaching anything other than Darwinism would require
that “all creation stories” be taught, this is a misleading argument. Many
myths about the origin of the world, such as the Coyote myth prominent in
Native American religions, make no claim to be scientific. See, e.g.,
Robert W. Lannan, Anthropology and Restless Spirits: The Native American
Graves Protection and Repatriation Act, and the Unresolved Issues of
Prehistoric Human Remains, 22 Harv.
Envtl. L. Rev. 369, 386 (1998) (describing Nez Perce account of “the
origins of people in North America” as one where coyote cuts “huge” monster up
with knife, then creates various Indian tribes from former monster). While such
stories can be taught in other courses in the curriculum, such as literature or
social studies, they should not be taught in a class concerned with efforts to
identify scientific theories regarding the origins issue.
321Astonishingly, those who claim that design theory is
merely religion disguised as science do not hesitate to enlist religion when it
suits their purposes. Eugenie Scott, Director of the National Center for
Science Education and one of the most frequent champions of a Darwin-only
presentation, has suggested that biology teachers invite their students to
survey community religious leaders:
A teacher in Minnesota told me that he had good luck
sending his students out at the beginning of the semester to interview their
pastors and priests about evolution. They came back somewhat astonished, “Hey!
Evolution is OK!” Even when there was diversity in opinion, with some religious
leaders accepting evolution as compatible with their theology and others
rejecting it, it was educational for the students to find out for themselves
that there was no single Christian perspective on evolution. The
survey-of-ministers approach may not work if the community is religiously
homogeneous, especially if that homogeneity is conservative Christian, but it
is something that some teachers might consider as a way of getting students’
fingers out of their ears.
Eugenie C. Scott, Dealing with Anti-evolutionism,
Reports of the National Center for
Science Education (visited Mar. 6, 2000)
<http://www.natcenscied.org/deal174.htm>.
322To be sure, in this era of interdisciplinary studies,
where biology textbooks frequently connect the social implications of biology
for environmental or ecological issues, it seems a little strange to treat the
metaphysical implications of the origins issues as though they were taboo in
the science class. However, the point to be emphasized is not that the
questions are unimportant or inappropriate, but rather that the methodology of
science proceeds from evidence to conclusions, whereas the methodology of a
social studies class permits the assertion of values or human intuition as the
starting point for discussion. Thus, the student's argument that naturalistic
evolution is true (or untrue) because it matches (or conflicts with) the
student's fundamental intuitions about human nature is appropriate in a
philosophy or social studies class, but not to a science classroom where
theories are judged according to their ability to explain evidence.
323See Reno v.
American Civil Liberties Union, 521 U.S. 844 (1997) (striking internet
restrictions as violating First Amendment).
324As noted earlier, one prominent Darwinist has suggested
precisely the kind of balanced approach that is advocated in this article. See
Provine, supra note 64 and accom-panying text.
325Boring v. Buncombe County Bd. of Educ., 136 F.3d 364,
371 (4th Cir. 1998).
326393 U.S. 503 (1969).
327Id. at 506.
Later in the opinion the Court stated:
The District Court concluded that the action of the
school authorities was reasonable because it was based upon their fear of a
disturbance from the wearing of the armbands. But, in our system,
undifferentiated fear or apprehension of disturbance is not enough to overcome
the right to freedom of expression. Any departure from absolute regimentation
may cause trouble. Any variation from the majority's opinion may inspire fear.
Any word spoken, in class, in the lunchroom, or on the campus, that deviates
from the views of another person may start an argument or cause a disturbance.
But our Constitution says we must take this risk . . . and
our history says that it is this sort of hazardous freedom—this kind of
openness—that is the basis of our national strength and of the independence and
vigor of Americans who grow up and live in this relatively permissive, often
disputatious, society.
In order for the State in the person of school
officials to justify prohibition of a particular expression of opinion, it must
be able to show that its action was caused by something more than a mere desire
to avoid the discomfort and unpleasantness that always accompany an unpopular
viewpoint.
Id. at 508–09
(citation omitted).
328Board of Educ., Island Trees Union Free Sch. Dist. No.
26 v. Pico, 457 U.S. 853, 870-71 (1982).
329Id. at 871.
330Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of the Univ. of Va.,
515 U.S. 819, 828 (1995) (plurality opinion) (citing Police Dep’t of Chicago v.
Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 96 (1972). See also City Council of Los Angeles v.
Taxpayers for Vincent, 466 U.S. 789, 804 (1984) (“The general principle that
has emerged from this line of cases is that the First Amendment forbids the
government to regulate speech in a way that favors some viewpoints or ideas at
the expense of others.”) (citing Bolger v. Youngs Drug Prod. Corp., 463 U.S.
60, 65 (1983); Consolidated Edison Co. v. Public Serv. Comm'n, 447 U.S. 530,
535-36 (1980); Carey v. Brown, 447 U.S. 455, 462-63 (1980); Young v. American
Mini Theatres, Inc. 427 U.S. 50, 63, 65, 67-68 (1976) (plurality opinion); Mosely,
408 U.S. at 95–96).
331See
Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 828 (plurality
opinion) (citing Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U.S., 622,
641-643 (1994)); see also Lamb’s Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free
Sch. Dist., 508 U.S. 384, 394 (1993) (allowing religious film to be shown on
public property after school hours).
332Rosenberger,
515 U.S. at 828.
333See Cornelius
v. NAACP Legal Defense and Educ. Fund, Inc., 473 U.S. 788 (1985)).
334See Rosenberger,
515 U.S. passim.
335See Lamb’s
Chapel, 508 U.S. at 394.
336515 U.S. 819 (1995) (plurality opinion).
337See id. at 839
(“More than once we have rejected the position that the Establishment Clause
even justifies, much less requires, a refusal to extend free speech rights to
religious speakers who participate in broad-reaching government programs
neutral in design.”) (citing Lamb’s Chapel, 508 U.S. at 393–94; Mergens,
496 U.S. at 248, 252; Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263, 274–75 (1981)).
338See id. at
827.
339See id. at
828.
340See id. at
829–30.
341Id. at 828.
342Id. at 829.
343Id. (citing
Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37, 46 (1983)).
344See id.; see
also Cornelius, 473 U.S. at 806 (discussing government prohibition
on speech content regulation in a nonpublic forum).
345Cornelius, 473
U.S at 806 (citing Perry, 460 U.S. at 49).
346Id. (citing
Lehman v. City of Shaker Heights, 418 U.S. 298 (1974)).
347See id.
(citing Perry, 460 U.S. at 49).
348See Lamb’s
Chapel, 508 U.S. at 394 (citing Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263, 271
(1981)).
349See Rosenberger,
515 U.S. at 842.
350See Peloza v.
Capistrano Unified Sch. Dist., 37 F.3d 517, 522 (9th Cir. 1994) (quoting Tinker,
393 U.S. at 506-07)).
351See Tinker,
393 U.S. at 512–13.
352Id. at 506–07.
353393 U.S. 97 (1968).
354See id. at 98.
355See id. at
98–99.
356See id. at
100.
357See id. at
104–06.
358Epperson, 393
U.S. at 104.
359Id. at 105
(quoting Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589, 603 (1967)).
360Id. at 107.
361Id. (citing Keyishian,
305 U.S. at 605–06.)
362See Westside
Community Bd. of Educ. v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226, 247–50 (1990).
363City Council of Los Angeles v. Taxpayers for Vincent,
466 U.S at 804.
364482 U.S. 578 (1986).
365See id. at
587.
366See id. at 589
(stating that “the Act does not . . . protect academic
freedom, but has the distinctly different purpose of discrediting [evolution
theory]”).
367See id. at
587.
368See id. at
593–94.
369See id. at
587.
370See id.
371Id. at 593–94
(citation omitted).
372See id. at
586.
373See id. at
593.
374See id. at
593–94.
375Id.
376Board of Educ. of Island Trees Union Free Sch. Dist.
No. 26 v. Pico, 457 U.S. 853, 871 (1982). See also Abood v. Detroit Bd.
of Educ., 431 U.S. 209 (1977) (noting that First Amendment principles
prohibited union and board of education from requiring any teacher to
contribute to support of ideological cause that teacher might oppose as
condition of hold-ing job as public school teacher).
377See Tinker,
393 U.S. 503.
378See Pico,
457 U.S. 853.
379482 U.S. 578 (1986).
380See Libraries
in Michigan District Will Carry Books Questioning Evolution, St. Louis Post Dispatch, Feb. 12, 1999,
at A7; Bruce Chapman, ‘Intelligent Design’ vs. ‘Materialism,’ Seattle Post-Intelligencer, Nov. 14,
1997, at A15.
381See Nancy
Young, Evolution Challenger Asks Court to Ban Textbook, Virginian-Pilot, May 26, 1997, at B1.